Florida State University Law Review Florida State University Law Review
Volume 28 Issue 1 Article 5
2000
The Contracting State The Contracting State
Jody Freeman
Follow this and additional works at: https://ir.law.fsu.edu/lr
Part of the Law Commons
Recommended Citation Recommended Citation
Jody Freeman,
The Contracting State
, 28 Fla. St. U. L. Rev. (2000) .
https://ir.law.fsu.edu/lr/vol28/iss1/5
This Article is brought to you for free and open access by Scholarship Repository. It has been accepted for
inclusion in Florida State University Law Review by an authorized editor of Scholarship Repository. For more
information, please contact efarrell@law.fsu.edu.
FLORIDA STATE UNIVERSITY
L
AW REVIEW
THE CONTRACTING STATE
Jody Freeman
V
OLUME 28
F
ALL 2000
N
UMBER 1
Recommended citation: Jody Freeman, The Contracting State, 28 FLA. ST. U. L. REV. 155
(2000).
155
THE CONTRACTING STATE
JODY FREEMAN*
I. INTRODUCTION.................................................................................................... 155
II. PRIVATIZATION.................................................................................................... 160
III. GOVERNMENT-PRIVATE CONTRACTS................................................................... 164
A. Objections to Contracting Out..................................................................... 169
1. Consequentialist Concerns.................................................................... 169
2. “Technocratic” Concerns........................................................................ 170
3. Ethical Concerns................................................................................... 172
4. Administrative Law Concerns.............................................................. 174
a. Examples.......................................................................................... 176
i. Nursing Homes........................................................................ 177
ii. Medicaid and Managed Care.................................................. 180
iii. Private Prisons......................................................................... 185
IV. REGULATORY CONTRACTS................................................................................... 189
A. Regulation as Negotiation........................................................................... 189
B. Experiments in “Contractual” Regulation................................................... 191
C. Objections to Regulatory Contracts............................................................. 198
1. The “Undemocratic” Critique................................................................ 198
2. Ousting Public Law Norms................................................................... 199
V. CONTRACT AS AN ACCOUNTABILITY MECHANISM ............................................... 201
VI. THE UNCOMFORTABLE INTERFACE OF PUBLIC LAW NORMS
AND PRIVATE LAW PRINCIPLES........................................................................... 207
VII. CONCLUSION....................................................................................................... 212
I. INTRODUCTION
The modern administrative state might aptly be dubbed “the con-
tracting state.” Around the world, governments appear to be both
shrinking and outsourcing many of their traditional functions to pri-
vate parties, sometimes indirectly by devolving power to local gov-
ernments that themselves depend heavily on private actors.
1
In the
United States, federal, state, and local governments now routinely
employ contracts with private providers to furnish services, deliver
benefits, and perform significant (and sometimes traditionally “pub-
lic”) functions.
2
Less visibly, a number of federal agencies have begun
* Professor of Law, University of California Los Angeles. I am grateful to Ann Carl-
son, Michael Asimow, Sharon Dolovich, Dan Guttman, Gillian Lester, Jim Rossi, J.B. Ruhl,
Jim Salzman, Mark Seidenfeld and the participants in this symposium for helpful com-
ments on earlier drafts. The article benefited as well from a workshop at the Washington
College of Law at American University. Thanks to Joanna Wolfe for excellent research as-
sistance. Jason Kellogg deserves credit for enormous editorial patience. Errors and omis-
sions are mine.
1. See generally SHEILA B. KAMERMAN & ALFRED J. KAHN, PRIVATIZATION AND THE
WELFARE STATE (1989).
2. Public sector reform in Britain has resulted in significant government downsizing
and contracting out. See KIERON WALSH, PUBLIC SERVICES AND MARKET MECHANISMS at xi
(1995); see also Murray Hunt, Constitutionalism and the Contractualisation of Government
in the United Kingdom, in THE PROVINCE OF ADMINISTRATIVE LAW 21 (Michael Taggart
156 FLORIDA STATE UNIVERSITY LAW REVIEW [Vol. 28:155
experimenting with contractual approaches to regulation as well,
sometimes pursuant to statutory mandates, and other times as part
of agency enforcement discretion.
3
Governments increasingly act in
all of their capacities, it seems, via contractual devices.
4
Despite the rising prominence of contract as an administrative
and regulatory instrument, its implications for administrative law
are not well understood. In this Article, I begin a much-needed dis-
cussion of contractual governance by focusing on two species of con-
tractcontracts to provide services or benefits (already well-
entrenched in the United States) and regulatory contracts (a nascent,
but noteworthy, development). I explain the practical and the theo-
retical problems these contracts pose, chief among which is their po-
tential to undermine accountability in decisionmaking.
Widespread contracting out of services or arguably “public” func-
tions could have dire consequences under some circumstancesif
legislatures systematically outsource their traditional functions and
use contracts with private parties to insulate decisions from constitu-
tional scrutiny, for example. Contracting could obscure traditional
lines of accountability, enabling legislatures to take credit for doing
little, while blaming private contractors for program failures.
5
Moreover, even with the best intentions, legislatures and their
agency delegates may lack the capacity to oversee compliance with
contractual terms. Absent a procedural right to participate in con-
tract negotiations, and without third-party rights of action, the bene-
ficiaries of these contracts may be left with no avenues for participa-
tion or redress. As a result, the pressure for government-private con-
tracts to absorb public law norms of fairness, rationality, and ac-
countability will only intensify if government increasingly employs
them to provide important services and outsource its traditional
functions. More broadly, widespread contracting out could wreak
havoc with the balance of power among the branches of government:
weakening the legislative and executive branches through fragmen-
ed., 1997). On the United Kingdom experience, see generally Peter Vincent-Jones, The
Regulation of Contractualisation in Quasi-markets for Public Services, 1999 PUBLIC LAW
304. In many countries, privatization has taken the form of selling state assets to the pri-
vate sector. See JOHN D. DONAHUE, THE PRIVATIZATION DECISION 6-7 (1989). In the United
States, where historically fewer assets have been state-owned, privatization has consisted
of contracting out and devolving power, as well as streamlining government activity. See
id. at 6-8.
3. See Jody Freeman, The Private Ro le in Public Governance, 75 N.Y.U. L. REV. 543,
636-38 (2000).
4. See id. at 548.
5. Some commentators believe that this already describes a good deal of governance.
See, e.g., JOEL F. HANDLER, DOWN FROM BUREAUCRACY (1996).
2000] CONTRACTING STATE 157
tation and delegation, and overburdening the judiciary with chal-
lenges to contractual schemes.
6
Contractual regulatory instruments raise different, but equally
serious concerns. The possibility that governments might negotiate
regulatory standards with the entities they are empowered to regu-
late strikes most traditional administrative law scholars as anath-
emaa recipe for either corporatism or capture. Treating regulations
as enforceable contracts could require governments to unilaterally
absorb the costs of changing conditions, or bind governments to the
bad bargains of their predecessors, a possibility that no longer seems
remote in light of recent Supreme Court jurisprudence.
7
Some commentators might think that regulatory contracts are in-
sufficiently similar to the phenomenon of contracting out to merit in-
clusion in a larger category of contractual instruments of governance.
In this view, contractual regulatory instruments emerge for distinct
reasons and cause different problems than widespread contracting
out.
8
Indeed, administrative law scholars tend to treat contractual
regulatory instruments as mere instances of agency discretion: op-
tional implementation tools designed to achieve the agency’s ulti-
mate goal. If the regulatory goal is lawful, and the agency’s exercise
of discretion remains within permissible bounds, then the use of con-
tract (as opposed to any other tool) as a method of implementation
seems unobjectionable. Seen in this light, contractual regulatory
tools raise familiar problems best solved by familiar measures. The
legislature might bar the use of contract through constraints on
agency discretion or specifically authorize the agency to use contract
as an implementation option. Either way, the issue is discretion; con-
tract is decidedly secondary.
Not all instances of discretion are alike, however, and the full im-
plications of these tools might best be glimpsed through the prism of
6. See David Mullan, Administrative Law at the Margins, in THE PROVINCE OF
ADMINISTRATIVE LAW, supra note 2, at 155-56 (arguing that judicial review may intensify
in response to privatization).
7. See United States v. Winstar Corp., 518 U.S. 839 (1996). I discuss this case in de-
tail. See infra notes 229-49 and accompanying text.
8. I thank Mark Niles and Jim Salzman for raising this objection to the inclusion of
regulatory contracts. They point out that the trend toward contracting out may have
emerged for different reasons than the trend toward using contract to implement regula-
tion, and they argue that this distinction ought to make a difference. Indeed, contracting
out may be a response to tightening government budgets, a generalized public antipathy
toward government, and the increasing ideological appeal of the market, whereas the
emergence of regulatory contracts might be explained by the need for greater flexibility in
executing regulatory responsibilities. To put a fine point on it, resorting to contractual
regulatory approaches might be nothing more than a few agencies’ defensive reaction to a
Republican Congress that disfavors environmental and health and safety regulation. Even
if this is true, however, the contractual nature of these innovationsand their emergence
at a time when other contractual approaches are also becoming widespreadbears noting,
and has some important implications for administrative law.
158 FLORIDA STATE UNIVERSITY LAW REVIEW [Vol. 28:155
contract. Regulatory contracts pose unique problems for administra-
tive law. Among other things, they depend heavily on private actors
that tend not to be bound by constitutional or administrative law
constraints.
9
Unlike the agency discretion perspective, the contrac-
tual lens brings this dependence on private actors, and its attendant
risks, into focus. It also highlights the potential conflict between the
government’s role as authoritative regulator and its role as contract-
ing partner, which even explicit legislative authorization cannot re-
solve. Finally, the contractual prism foregrounds the ways in which
contract, as a particular mode of decisionmaking, might uniquely ob-
struct or facilitate public participation.
Thus, the conceptualization of seemingly different types of con-
tracts as a family of related tools is meant to supplement, rather
than displace, other useful perspectives. It treats contractual regula-
tory tools not merely as potentially problematic instances of discre-
tion, but as part of an emerging “contract culture”a trend toward
fragmented and decentralized governance that includes, but is not
limited to, contracting out government functions. Among other
things, that trend may impose great pressure on courts to reconcile
principles of private contract law, which do not necessarily afford
agencies deference, with principles of administrative law, which do.
10
At the same time, despite their significant risks, government-
private contracts of all types might nonetheless produce important
benefits that we should not overlook. The rise of contract may signal
not so much the retreat of the state as a reconfiguration of the state’s
role in governance. That reconfiguration could conceivably amount to
a net gain in accountability, or at least not a net loss. In an era of
greater private involvement in every facet of administration and
regulation, contracts can themselves function as potentially crucial
accountability mechanisms.
11
For example, contractual provisions
may allow third-party beneficiaries to hold the contracting parties to
9. See Freeman, supra note 3, at 574-591 (describing the extent to which private ac-
tors escape constitutional and other legal constraints). The Administrative Procedure Act,
5 U.S.C. §§ 551-559, 701-706 (1994 & Supp. V 1999), specifically exempts government con-
tracts from the procedural requirements of notice and comment. See § 553 (a)(2).
10. See WALSH, supra note 2, at 136-37 (referring to the emergence of a contract cul-
ture); see also DONAHUE, supra note 2, at 6-8. See generally GENERAL ACCOUNTING OFFICE,
GAO/HEHS-98-6, SOCIAL SERVICE PRIVATIZATION: EXPANSION POSES CHALLENGES IN
ENSURING ACCOUNTABILITY FOR PROGRAM RESULTS (1997) (documenting expanded privati-
zation of social services and analyzing implications for accountability), available at
http://www.access.gpo.gov/su_docs/aces/aces160.shtml.
11. Although private parties have always shared responsibility for governance to
greater or lesser degrees, their roles have diversified and expanded, sometimes into terri-
tory once regarded as the exclusive province of the state. See generally Freeman, supra
note 3. In light of this expansion of private authority, some scholars have argued that there
is no longer a justification for treating public and private power differently: that we ought
to constrain the private exercise of discretion just as we do public agencies. See id. at 574-
75.
2000] CONTRACTING STATE 159
their commitments. Contracts could also enable government agencies
to accomplish indirectly what, for legal or political reasons, they can-
not achieve directly. As with grants-in-aid between the federal and
state governments, public-private contracts could be a means of ex-
tending government priorities and policies to private actors, and of
exacting concessions and gains that might otherwise be beyond the
government’s regulatory reach.
Like settlements, regulatory contracts could provide the parties
more flexibility than does the formal enforcement process. This flexi-
bility accrues of course not only to the private contracting party, but
to government as well. Through regulatory contract, private actors
may agree to conform to substantive regulatory requirements or
adopt procedural norms that are otherwise inapplicable to them or
unenforceable against them. In addition, regulatory contracts might
function as disclosure mechanisms that identify and specify regula-
tory goals, which might in turn enable both government overseers
and third-party auditors to monitor progress toward those goals. Un-
der the right circumstances then, regulatory contracts could prove at
least no less effective and democratic than other regulatory instru-
ments.
Whether one welcomes or fears the rise of contract as an adminis-
trative and regulatory tool, however, existing doctrines and theoreti-
cal frameworks will need to adapt to its emergence. Contractual in-
struments pose a host of doctrinal and theoretical problems for which
administrative law provides no ready answers. Administrative law
theory has yet to explore, let alone internalize, such a contractual
model of governance. Each of the competing theories of the field
public interest,
12
pluralist,
13
civic republican,
14
and public choice
15
consists at its core of a distinctive understanding of the agency’s
function
16
and a unique justification for judicial review, but they
12. See, e.g., Richard B. Stewart, The Reformation of American Administrative Law ,
88 HARV. L. REV. 1667, 1763 (1975) (describing public interest theory as aimed at advocat-
ing representation of “widely diffused” interests that otherwise would not prompt indi-
viduals to undertake litigation).
13. See id. at 1760-61 (noting the emergence of public participation in agency deci-
sionmaking as a way to improve decisions and increase public participation in the process).
14. For a representative civic republican account, see Mark Seidenfeld, A Civic Re-
publican Justification for the Bureaucratic State, 105 HARV. L. REV. 1511 (1992).
15. See, e.g., Mathew D. McCubbins et al., Administrative Procedures as Instruments
of Political Control, 3 J.L. ECON. & ORG. 243 (1987) (noting that in the absence of over-
sight, agency officials are likely to make decisions reflecting personal preferences derived
from private political values, personal career o bjectives, and aversion to effort).
16. They are, respectively, an institution devoted to implementing legislation in the
public interest, see Freeman, supra note 3, at 558-59; a broker of stakeholder interests, see
id. at 559-60; an expert body deliberating in a public-regarding way, see id. at 559; or an
agent of self-interested legislators, see id. at 561-63.
160 FLORIDA STATE UNIVERSITY LAW REVIEW [Vol. 28:155
share a hierarchical vision of governance.
17
A conception of the gov-
ernment agency as “contracting partner” fits comfortably with none
of these accounts. As a result, the complement of oversight mecha-
nisms currently envisioned by these theories to constrain agency ac-
tion might be inadequateor wholly inappropriatefor the problems
that arise in the contracting state.
18
In Part II of this Article, I describe how privatization trends in the
United States have created an environment in which public-private
contracts are likely to flourish. The bulk of the Article is devoted to
the two species of such contracts that appear to pose the most diffi-
culty for administrative lawcontracts for social services and regu-
latory contracts. In Parts III and IV, I provide examples of contracts
for social services and regulatory contracts, respectively, and discuss
the most frequent objections to them. I argue in Part V that despite
the risks they pose, both kinds of contracts offer some attractive
benefits, and I explore in particular their potential to function as ac-
countability mechanisms. I conclude by describing how these ar-
rangements could create an uncomfortable confrontation between
public law principles of deference to agency action and private law
principles of contract interpretation.
II. PRIVATIZATION
The rise of contract as an administrative and regulatory instru-
ment in the United States has occurred in the context of a global pri-
vatization movement in which governments around the world have
privatized state industries and undergone significant public sector
reform.
19
Over the last twenty years, following the Thatcher govern-
ment’s lead in Great Britain, numerous liberal democracies such as
New Zealand, Australia, and Canada have adopted aggressive re-
forms aimed at developing markets for the provision of most social
services, including education, health care, job training, housing, mu-
nicipal services, and the like.
20
The privatization of state industries
17. With the possible exception of public choice theory, which is arguably more ex-
planatory than normative. It is not difficult to imagine normative proposals that might
flow from the public choice account, however. For more on public choice theory’s impact on
administrative law, see Freeman, supra note 3.
18. While somewhat helpful as a starting point, the law governing traditional gov-
ernment procurement of goods and services addresses only a narrow subset of government
contracts. The procurement framework is either imperfect or wholly unsuitable for re-
sponding to the more widespread use of contract to deliver services or perform arguably
public functions. At the same time, the law governing the interpretation and enforcement
of regulatory contracts remains in flux. See United States v. Winstar Corp., 518 U.S. 839
(1996).
19. See DONAHUE, supra note 2, at 6-7.
20. See WALSH, supra note 2, at 26 (describing the five major mechanisms that make
up public sector reform: user charges for services, opening services to competitive tende r-
2000] CONTRACTING STATE 161
together with the shift to internal markets, competitive tendering,
and contracting out has created new relationships between public
and private actors in these countries and forced governments to de-
vise measures for structuring and monitoring the new arrange-
ments.
21
Kieron Walsh describes the result as a form of organization
that is “neither market nor hierarchy, but which lies rather uncom-
fortably between the two.”
22
These trends might be described as a
shift from hierarchical relationships to contractual ones.
23
In the United States, the privatization movement has primarily
taken the form of increased contracting out of government services,
devolution, and streamlining government.
24
These three develop-
ments have occurred simultaneously, and they have been mutually
reinforcing. Although privatization has developed into an ideological
movement in the United States only in the last twenty years, relying
on the private sector to perform “public” functions as a practical mat-
ter has a long history.
25
Since at least the post-war period, the federal government, along
with state and local governments, has increasingly depended on pri-
vate contractors to provide a wide variety of goods and services not
only for government consumption but for public consumption as well,
from weapons systems to environmental impact statements to social
services, including health care, welfare, day care, job training, infra-
structure maintenance, and waste collection.
26
The trend toward pri-
vatizing social services has accelerated and intensified in the last two
decades, however, as a result of a concerted effort by the federal gov-
ernment (beginning with the Reagan Administration) to devolve
power to lower levels of government and spur the private provision of
ing or contracting out work, introducing internal markets, devolving financial control, and
establishing parts of the organization on an agency basis).
21. In the United Kingdom and elsewhere, the state engages in three primary modes
of contracting: internal contracting, competitive tendering, and the contracting out of se r-
vices. See id. at 121.
22. Id. at xviii.
23. See id. (observing that “[a]uthority relations are being redefined as contracts” and
that “[t]he public service is becoming a more or less integrated network of organisations
that relate through contract and price rather than authority”).
24. See DONAHUE, supra note 2, at 6-8.
25. See LESTER M. SALAMON, PARTNERS IN PUBLIC SERVICE 5 (1995).
26. See id. at 5-6, 42-43. Until recently, contracts for health, welfare, and similar so-
cial services primarily went to nonprofits. See id. at 5. This has begun to change, however,
as economic conditions make social welfare delivery increasingly attractive to for-profit
firms. See id. at 10. For-profit participation has been on the rise in recent years. For-profit
nursing homes increased 140% between 1960 and 1976. See Eleanor D. Kinney, Private Ac-
creditation as a Substitute for Direct Government Regulation in Public Health Insurance
Programs: When Is It Appropriate?, LAW & CONTEMP. PROBS., Autumn 1994, at 47, 51. By
1980, more than 90% of nursing homes were privately owned. See Patricia A. Butler, As-
suring the Quality of Care and Life in Nursing Homes: The Dilemma of Enforcement, 57
N.C. L. REV. 1317, 1337 n.96 (1979).
162 FLORIDA STATE UNIVERSITY LAW REVIEW [Vol. 28:155
publicly financed services.
27
Notably, during this period the percent-
age of for-profit organizations involved in service delivery has ex-
panded and the universe of functions thought suitable for privatiza-
tion appears to have enlarged.
28
Both the federal and state govern-
ments have turned to for-profit firms to run detention centers and
prisons for example, a function once thought to be the exclusive prov-
ince of government.
The devolution of authority from federal to state and local gov-
ernments has contributed to the rise of contracting out, as lower lev-
els of government turn to private actors in order to help execute their
new responsibilities. Welfare reform offers a recent example of this
phenomenon. The Personal Responsibility and Work Opportunity
Reconciliation Act of 1996
29
(PRA)which abolished the federal enti-
tlement to financial assistance known as Aid to Families with De-
pendent Children, providing instead a system of block grants to the
states
30
seems to be intensifying the privatization of benefits ad-
ministration in at least some states.
31
Similarly, the devolutionary
aspects of the Balanced Budget Act of 1997
32
appear to have acceler-
ated state reliance on private organizations, including managed care
organizations, to deliver care to the Medicaid population.
33
At the same time, recent efforts by the Clinton Administration to
streamline government and promote “public-private partnerships”
seem likely to foster greater reliance on private sector institutions.
Vice President Gore’s high profile effort to “reinvent” government,
adopted in the National Performance Review, cut the budgets of ex-
27. See SALAMON, supra note 25, at 6-8; John J. DiIulio, Jr. & Richard P. Nathan, In-
troduction to MEDICAID AND DEVOLUTION 1 (Frank J. Thompson & John J. DiIulio, Jr. eds.,
1998) (referring to the 1990s as “the decade of devolution”).
28. See SALAMON, supra note 25, at 42-43.
29. Pub. L. No. 104-193, 110 Stat. 2105.
30. See id. § 103(a), 110 Stat. at 2112-60 (codified as amended at 42 U.S.C. §§ 601-619
(Supp. V 1999)). The Act attaches relatively few conditions to the block grants and allows
states to design benefit programs and eligibility requirements. See id.
31. See David J. Kennedy, Due Process in a Privatized Welfare System, 64 BROOK. L.
REV. 231, 231 (1998) (describing the PRA, which allows states to use private corporations
to operate benefit programs).
32. Pub. L. No. 105-33, 111 Stat. 251.
33. In addition to increasing state flexibility to set payment levels, see id. §§ 4711-
4715, 111 Stat. at 507-09 (codified as amended at 42 U.S.C. §§ 1396a to 1396r-7), the Act
allows states to mandate enrollment in managed care programs without applying for fed-
eral waivers. See § 4702(a), 111 Stat. at 494-95 (codified as amended at 42 U.S.C. §
1396d(a), 1396d(t)). The waiver process had enabled rigorous federal oversight of state re-
liance on managed care organizations serving the Medicaid population. See MEDICAID AND
DEVOLUTION, supra note 27, at 122. The authors argue that devolution is a complex, in-
cremental process, and that it ought not to be defined as wholesale federal withdrawal
from a policy field. See id. at 7. Enhanced state flexibility over the Medicaid program has
coincided with the general shift from fee-for-service to managed care, and that shift has in-
troduced new players (such as Managed Care Organizations) into the Medicaid regime.
The combination of devolution and managed care has enhanced the already significant role
that contract plays in securing compliance with Medicaid program requirements.
2000] CONTRACTING STATE 163
ecutive agencies across the board, streamlined bureaucracies
34
through a variety of measures, and sought to promote regulatory in-
novation in the form of consensus-based decisionmaking and public-
private partnerships.
35
As both a rhetorical and a practical matter,
these measures invite increased reliance on the private sector.
This combination of eventscontracting out, devolution, and pub-
lic sector reformhas created an environment in which public-
private contract seems likely to flourish. And although commentators
have debated the merits of privatization from an economic and politi-
cal perspective
36
and sought to identify the conditions under which
privatization will produce efficiency gains,
37
the implications of priva-
tization for administrative law remain unclear. At first blush, con-
tractual instruments might strike administrative law scholars as un-
interesting or unproblematic. They do not appear to disrupt settled
categories of agency action, challenge established explanations of the
administrative process, or impugn traditional justifications for judi-
cial review.
38
However, government-private contracts have the poten-
34. See The Federal Workforce Restructuring Act of 1994, Pub. L. No. 103-226, 108
Stat. 111 (1994) (codified as amended in scattered sections of 5 U.S.C.) (requiring a redu c-
tion of 272,900 civilian jobs by the end of fiscal year 1999). The federal civilian work force
has decreased from 2.16 million full-time equivalents (FTE) in 1993 to 1.8 million FTEs in
1998, a decrease of 360,000 FTEs. See OFFICE OF MANAGEMENT & BUDGET, ANALYTICAL
PERSPECTIVES, BUDGET OF THE UNITED STATES GOVERNMENT, FISCAL YEAR 2000, at 247
(1999) [hereinafter ANALYTICAL PERSPECTIVES], available at http://w3.access.gpo.gov/
usbudget/fy2000/pdf/spec.pdf.
35. See, e.g., OFFICE OF THE VICE PRESIDENT, ACCOMPANYING REPORT OF THE
NATIONAL PERFORMANCE REVIEW: ENVIRONMENTAL PROTECTION AGENCY 23-27, 51-52
(1993) [hereinafter EPA ACCOMPANYING REPORT] (companion document to VICE
PRESIDENT AL GORE, FROM RED TAPE TO RESULTS: CREATING A GOVERNMENT THAT WORKS
BETTER AND COSTS LESS (1993)), http://www.npr.gov/library/reports.epa.html; VICE
PRESIDENT AL GORE, FROM RED TAPE TO RESULTS: CREATING A GOVERNMENT THAT WORKS
BETTER AND COSTS LESS: REPORT OF THE NATIONAL PERFORMANCE REVIEW passim (1993),
http://www.npr.gov/library/nprrpt/annrpt/redtpe93/index.html.
36. See,e.g., Andrei Shleifer, State Versus Private Ownership, J. ECON. PERSP., Fall
1998, at 133, 141-44 (1998) (analyzing politics of government ownership and privatization
and noting that political considerations not only strengthen the case for privatization, but
in fact drive the decision to privatize); see also DONAHUE, supra note 2, at 11-12 (arguing
that the values of efficiency and accountability of public and private arrangements in “o r-
ganizational architecture” should be reorganized in a way that will best deliver public
goods and services). Privatization does not guarantee accountability; however, in some
cases, private ownership has reduced access to information that was more easily available
under public ownership. See C. Graham & T. Prosser, “Rolling Back the Frontiers”? The
Privatisation of State Enterprises, in A READER ON ADMINISTRATIVE LAW 63, 80-86 (D.J.
Galligan ed., 1996); see also HANDLER, supra note 5, at 86-90 (discussing public-private
contracts that lack competition and cause a decrease in efficiency and accountability).
37. See, e.g., DONAHUE, supra note 2, at 56-78.
38. Much administrative law scholarship consists of debates over statutory interpre-
tation and standards of judicial review of agency action. See, e.g., Colin S. Diver, Statutory
Interpretation in the Administrative State, 133 U. PA. L. REV. 549 (1985); Richard J. Pierce,
Jr., Chevron and Its Aftermath: Judicial Review of Agency Interpretations of Statutory Pro-
visions, 41 VAND. L. REV. 301 (1988). Another significant body of administrative law con-
cerns itself with the advantages and disadvantages of legislative controls, both formal and
164 FLORIDA STATE UNIVERSITY LAW REVIEW [Vol. 28:155
tial to do all three. In an era in which private actors play significant
roles in every aspect of governance,
39
contract is both a crucial ad-
ministrative policy instrument and a potential source of accountabil-
ity.
III. GOVERNMENT-PRIVATE CONTRACTS
Procurement contracts for goods and services are the most famil-
iar form of government contracting and, ironically, the least prob-
lematic from an administrative law perspective.
40
As a matter of
course, all levels of government contract with private providers for
goods and services, ranging from weapons systems to office supplies.
The federal government has established an elaborate body of pro-
curement law that governs such purchases.
41
It consists of a highly
detailed bidding, award, and contract management process. Of all
the “contract-like” arrangements into which government enters, pro-
curement contracts most closely resemble traditional commercial
contracts. And yet, federal procurement requires contractors to follow
strict, government-unique product specifications and contract rules
and regulations.
42
Indeed, despite their apparent similarity to com-
informal. See, e.g., Stephen Breyer, The Legislative Veto After Chadha, 72 GEO. L.J. 785
(1984); see also Mathew D. McCubbins et al., supra note 15.
39. For examples, see Freeman, supra note 3, at 547. See also SALAMON, supra note
25, at 42 (describing the phenomenon of “third-party government,” in which government
depends on a host of third-party institutions to carry out its missions). Administrative law
theory has largely ignored the private role in governance, focusing instead on the relation-
ships among legislatures, agencies, and courts. For an explanation of the roots of agency-
centered analysis, see Jody Freeman, Private Parties, Public Functions and the New Ad-
ministrative Law, reprinted in 52 ADMIN L. REV. 813, 816-17 (2000). See also Vincent-
Jones, supra note 2, at 311-12 (conceiving of the problem of regulation in terms of deploy-
ment and interaction of a variety of regulatory resources “fragmented and dispersed among
. . . state and non-state bodies”).
40. This is not to say that the procurement process functions efficiently or account-
ably. Federal military procurement has been famously corrupt and inefficient. See
DONAHUE, supra note 2, at 101-03.
41. Procurement contracts must conform to elaborate statutory and regulatory re-
quirements. The principal requirements are contained in Titles 10 and 41 of the United
States Code, see 10 U.S.C. §§ 2202, 2301-2331 (1994); 41 U.S.C. §§251-266 (1994 & Supp.
IV 1998), and the Federal Acquisition Regulation (FAR), 48 C.F.R. ch. 1 (1999). The Title
10 provisions cover procurement by the Armed Forces, Coast Guard, and NASA. See 10
U.S.C. § 2303. The Title 41 provisions cover procurement by the federal government gen-
erally and executive agencies. See 41 U.S.C. § 252. The FAR establishes highly detailed
procedures that govern every aspect of the procurement process including notice, competi-
tion, award, contract method, and contract management. See 48 C.F.R. pt. 1 (1999). In ad-
dition, each federal agency has been given authority to promulgate supplementary regula-
tions that apply to its own procurement process. See 48 C.F.R. § 1.301(a) (1999). Chapter
16 of Title 40 establishes the General Services Administration and gives the Administrator
of that agency the power to prescribe procurement regulations for the federal government.
See 40 U.S.C. § 751 (1994).
42. See sources cited supra note 41. The regime has attracted substantial criticism for
overly burdening companies doing business with the government and for unnecessarily in-
flating prices and wasting taxpayer money. See Christopher F. Corr & Kristina Zissis,
2000] CONTRACTING STATE 165
mercial contracts, procurement contracts consistently favor govern-
ment in a number of ways, by permitting termination for conven-
ience, for example, and by limiting the remedies available to private
contractors in the event of government breach.
43
Although fraud and abuse frequently occur in the procurement
process, as a conceptual matter, contracts to purchase “commercial”
goods and services directly for government consumption are less
troubling to administrative law than two other kinds of contracts:
those that allow private actors to provide services for third parties
and those that enable contractors to play significant roles imple-
menting laws or otherwise performing the work of government agen-
cies. The traditional procurement model, which consists of a highly
technocratic approach to contract designdetailed specifications,
elaborate procedures, formal agency supervisionmay be somewhat
amenable to controlling the excesses of commercial procurement, but
it may be too limited to address the much more substantial issues
that arise when government contracts out social services and tradi-
tionally governmental functions.
Moving away from procurement of goods for government con-
sumption, we see that all levels of government contract with private
providers for the delivery of social services and benefits such as
health care, welfare benefits, job training, day care, and education.
44
Convergence and Opportunity: The WTO Government Procurement Agreement and U.S.
Procurement Reform, 18 N.Y.L. SCH. J. INTL & COMP. L. 303, 314 (1999); Steven Kelman,
Buying Commercial: An Introduction and Framework, 27 PUB. CONT. L.J. 249, 250-51
(1998). In response to such criticisms, Congress passed the Federal Acquisition Streamlin-
ing Act of 1994, Pub. L. No. 103-355, 108 Stat. 3243 (codified as amended in scattered sec-
tions of 10, 15, and 41 U.S.C.), and the Federal Acquisition Reform Act of 1996 (FARA),
Pub. L. No. 104-106, Div. D, 110 Stat. 186, 642 (codified as amended in scattered sections
of 10, 15, 18, 22, 31, and 41 U.S.C.), to simplify acquisition procedures and decrease pro-
curement of government-specific products by increasing commercial purchases. FARA spe-
cifically called for the full and open competition requirements governing procurement to be
balanced with efficiency. See FARA § 4101(a)(2) (codified at 10 U.S.C. § 2304(j) (Supp. V
1999); Patrick E. Tolan, Jr., Government Contracting with Small Businesses in the Wake of
the Federal Acquisition Streamlining Act, the Federal Acquisition Reform Act, and Ada-
rand: Small Business as Usual?, 44 A.F. L. REV. 75, 79-80 & n.28 (1998).
43. See Gillian Hadfield, Of Sovereignty and Contract: Damages for Breach of Con-
tract by Government, 8 S. CAL. INTERDISC. L.J. 467, 488-95 (1999).
44. See, e.g., BURTON A. WEISBROD, THE NONPROFIT ECONOMY (1988); see also
DONAHUE, supra note 2, at 179, 219-20 (discussing job training and health care contracts
between government and private providers); SALAMON, supra note 25, at 10 (describing the
growth of for-profit organizations in the social welfare field). Although secondary school
education is still largely publicly provided, there are increasing trends toward privatiza-
tion. California education secretary Gary Hart said recently that one of the major issues
facing primary and secondary education is “the trend toward privatization.” Gary Hart,
Presentation Before the UCLA Faculty of Law (Sept. 18, 2000). Not only is there a trend
toward contracting out services like bus transportation and computer services, but gov-
ernments are also contracting out instruction. For example, a San Diego organization
called AVID provides half of all California high schools with a college prep curriculum
aimed at low-income students. See id.
166 FLORIDA STATE UNIVERSITY LAW REVIEW [Vol. 28:155
Private actors also provide amenities such as water and power and
furnish basic municipal services such as waste collection.
45
To fully
appreciate the context in which contracting out of this sort has flour-
ished, one must understand federal grants-in-aid, which are the
funding vehicles through which the federal government enables and
encourages state and local governments to achieve its policy goals.
46
Federal grants resemble contracts themselves
47
but are more ac-
curately described as conditional awards of funding.
48
They are di-
vided into mandatory and discretionary grants and again into cate-
I focus on the supply of such services rather than the demand for them (which might also
be contracted out, i.e., government might just abandon its role in determining whether a
service or function is needed). Although state and local governments may follow the pro-
curement model when contracting with private providers to deliver these services or bene-
fits, I distinguish these contracts from the traditional procurement context because the
services are for the benefit of third parties; these are not goods and services for the gov-
ernment’s own use.
45. The most widely privatized social service appears to be solid waste disposal. See
Steven C. Deller, Local Government Structure, Devolution, and Privatization, 20 REV.
AGRIC. ECON. 135, 136, 143 (1998).
46.
Spending on grants has grown from $7 billion in 1960 to $135.3 billion in 1990 to
$246.1 billion in 1998. Total federal grants as a percent of state and local expenditures has
ranged from 19% in 1960 to a high of 31% in 1980 to 25% in 1998. See ANALYTICAL
PERSPECTIVES, supra note 34, at 236. Medicaid is the largest grant program, receiving
$101.2 billion in 1998. See id. at 244. The federal government also relies extensively on
grants and cooperative agreements with states and local government to effect legislative
and administrative purposes. See 31 U.S.C. §§ 6304(1), 6305(1) (1994). These are known as
“domestic assistance” contracts because they enable the federal government to carry out a
“public purpose of support or stimulation authorized by a law of the United States.” Id.
However, they are not contracts. Compare 31 U.S.C. §§ 6304(1), 6305(1) (addressing grants
and cooperative agreements), with 31 U.S.C. § 6303 (1),(2) (1994) (addressing procurement
contracts). See also PAUL G. DEMBLING & MALCOM S. MASON, ESSENTIALS OF GRANT LAW
PRACTICE 12-13 (1991).
47. See DEMBLING & MASON, supra note 46, at 1-8. While analogous in some respects
to contracts, grants are not, strictly speaking, contracts. They are domestic assistance ve-
hiclesfunding mechanisms through which the federal government enables and encour-
ages state and local government to accomplish federal goals. Because federal grants offer
conditional inducements, they allow the federal government to accomplish indirectly what
it cannot mandate directly. In exchange for federal funding, recipient governments must
comply with certain conditions, which vary with the type of grant.
Analyzing these agreements using conventional contract analysis proves limited. Among
other things, they do not conform to the usual requirements of offer and acceptance. For
example, sometimes the agency attaches special conditions to the grant after it accepts the
application. Normally this would be a counter-offer, but in the world of grants, the agency’s
conditional award constitutes acceptance. See id. at 82. As another example, judicial re-
view of denials of discretionary grants is limited because of principles of deference to
agency action that would not apply to two private parties. See id. at 78-79. Decisions to
award discretionary grants are considered by courts to be informal policy making, a mode
of agency action over which courts hesitate to tread too heavily. See id. at 79. In essence,
the fact that one “contractual” partner is the government makes it difficult to interpret
them using conventional contract analysis. See id. at 8, 82.
48. See, e.g., South Dakota v. Dole, 483 U.S. 203, 223 (1987). The procedures, condi-
tions, remedies, enforcement, and overall administration of grants differ from the laws and
regulations governing federal procurement contracts as well as from commercial contracts.
See DEMBLING & MASON, supra note 46, at 3.
2000] CONTRACTING STATE 167
gorical (narrow purpose) and block grants (wide purpose).
49
Discre-
tionary grants are authorized by statute to further a specific purpose,
such as medical research or education, and are more likely to be di-
rectly provided to nongovernmental (chiefly nonprofit) organiza-
tions.
50
Federal agencies do not possess the inherent power to enter
grant agreements as they do procurement contracts. Instead, Con-
gress must explicitly provide for grants in legislation and authorize
appropriations for the grant. As a result, there is no uniform statu-
tory framework for grants as there is for procurement and they are
subject to a variety of government-wide and agency-specific condi-
tions. These conditions derive not only from statutes but from execu-
tive orders, agency regulations, grant policy manuals published by
particular agencies,
51
and recommendations from Office of Manage-
ment and Budget (OMB) circulars.
52
The grant system not only allows the federal government to ad-
vance its substantive policy goals, but it also enables the federal gov-
ernment to indirectly regulate state and local governments and ulti-
mately to impose conditions on the private providers of social ser-
vices. As a condition of grants, Congress can demand conformity with
its socioeconomic policies (such as anti-discrimination, environ-
mental, and labor standards) as well as administrative and fiscal
policies (such as compliance with record-keeping and inspection and
auditing requirements).
53
The power of these tools as instruments of
policy is particularly striking now, as the Supreme Court’s federal-
ism jurisprudence makes direct federal regulation of the states in-
creasingly difficult.
54
Conditional inducements in the form of grants-
in-aid fall within Congress’ Article I spending power.
55
Because a
49. See DEMBLING & MASON, supra note 46, at 31.
50. Discretionary grants differ significantly from procurement contracts in that they
permit agencies considerably more discretion in selecting grant awards, and accountability
for compliance with their terms seems more contextually driven and ad hoc. See id. at 69.
Discretionary grants are also distinguishable from procurement contracts in that they of-
ten amount to investments under conditions of uncertainty. See id. at 70.
51. See, e.g., DEPARTMENT OF HEALTH AND HUMAN SERVS., GRANTS ADMINISTRATION
MANUAL (1988), http://www.hhs.gov/grantsnet/admins/gam/gamanual.htm.
52. By statute, mandatory grants entitle an applicant to the grant if the applicant
meets specified criteria. See DEMBLING & MASON, supra note 46, at 33. Termination or de-
nial of nondiscretionary grants often entitles potential recipients to a formal trial-type
hearing before an administrative law judge. Discretionary grants do not typically offer
such procedural remedies.
53. For example, in Dole, 483 U.S. 203, the Supreme Court held that Congress’s use of
conditional grants to indirectly encourage states to conform to national concerns like a uni-
form drinking age was a valid use of its spending power.
54. See Printz v. United States, 521 U.S. 898, 935 (1997) (holding that Congress can-
not circumvent New York by commanding state officials to enforce a federal regulatory
program); New York v. United States, 505 U.S. 144, 149 (1992) (holding that the federal
government cannot compel a state to take title to its radioactive waste).
55. See U.S. CONST. art. I, § 8, cl. 1. Congress can regulate state policy indirectly
through the inducement of federal money. The spending power is not, however, unlimited.
168 FLORIDA STATE UNIVERSITY LAW REVIEW [Vol. 28:155
conditional grant is a “carrot” that a state can refuse, rather than a
“stick” that it cannot, even heavily conditional grants that require
states to pass legislation are not considered to be unconstitutionally
“coercive” intrusions into state sovereignty.
56
Much of this indirect
regulation would undoubtedly be struck down by the Court if it were
imposed directly. Thus, the grant conditions themselves become po-
tentially critical accountability mechanisms in an era of privatiza-
tion. They offer the federal government residual control over state
and local governments which must, in turn, regulate private grant
recipients to ensure that they comply with the grant conditions. The
grant device effectively enables the federal government to purchase
services for the benefit of third parties and regulate the delivery of
the services simultaneously.
57
For example, when a state wishes to receive federal Medicaid
funding, it must file a state plan that assures compliance with vari-
ous provisions of the Social Security Act, the Balanced Budget Act,
and a host of federal regulations promulgated by the Department of
Health and Human Services (HHS).
58
Compliance with these re-
quirements is a condition of receiving the program funds. Among
other things, federal regulations include requirements that apply to
contracts between the state agency and the private institutions that
ultimately deliver health care, including hospitals and managed care
organizations (MCOs).
59
The Supreme Court has articulated a four-prong test for assessing the constitutionality of
a conditional grant pursuant to the spending power: the power must be exercised in pu r-
suit of the general welfare; the conditions must be unambiguously stated; the conditions
must relate to a federal interest in particular national projects or programs; and Congress
cannot induce states to engage in activities that would themselves be unconstitutional. See
Dole, 483 U.S. at 207-08 (upholding a statute conditioning the receipt of highway funds on
adoption of a minimum drinking age of 21). The Court has struck down a conditional grant
only once. See United States v. Butler, 297 U.S. 1, 68 (1936) (invalidating a statute author-
izing payments to farmers who agreed to curtail acreage or production). The curtailment
scheme in Butler went “beyond the presumptive powers of Congress.” Albert J. Rosenthal,
Conditional Federal Spending and the Constitution, 39 STAN. L. REV. 1103, 1126 (1987).
Subsequent case law backed away from the Butler holding. See id. at 1113; see also Kath-
leen M. Sullivan, Unconstitutional Conditions, 102 HARV. L. REV. 1415, 1415 (1989) (de m-
onstrating that the Court has subjected conditions that interfere with individual rights to
heightened scrutiny). Conditioned grants are a staple of cooperative federalism and are
common in environmental statutes. For example, section 179 of the Clean Air Act condi-
tions receipt of federal highway funds upon compliance with the Act. See 42 U.S.C. § 7509
(1994). But see Cass R. Sunstein, Is the Clean Air Act Unconstitutional?, 98 MICH. L. REV.
303 (1999).
56. See Dole, 483 U.S. at 211-12 (differentiating between financial “encouragement”
and financial “coercion”).
57. This duality of roles is not insignificant. See Michael W. Graf, The Determination
of Property Rights in Public Contracts After Winstar v. United States: Where Has the Su-
preme Court Left Us?, 38 NAT. RESOURCES J. 197, 206 (1998) (noting the “two distinct gov-
ernment contractual models”government as “market participant” and government as
regulatorand criticizing Winstar for failing to distinguish them).
58. See 42 U.S.C. § 1396 (1994); 42 C.F.R. pts. 430-56 (1999).
59. See 42 C.F.R. pt. 434 (1999).
2000] CONTRACTING STATE 169
The relationship between the federal agency responsible for Medi-
caid oversight (the Health Care Financing Administration) and the
doctors and nurses who ultimately provide health care to Medicaid
eligible patients is therefore highly attenuated. However, it is
through a series of contractual agreementsfederal government
with state, state with health care institutions, and institutions with
providersthat the federal government exercises coercive power over
health care delivery.
In addition to providing the funding stream for contracts that de-
liver social services to third-party beneficiaries, government grants
also enable large transfers of money to private contractors to perform
executive work that we associate with the “civil service.”
60
Numerous
federal agencies rely heavily on a private work force to assist them in
implementing laws and regulations.
61
While I focus in this Article on
services and functions that contractors deliver directly to third-party
beneficiaries, the extent to which agencies rather invisibly rely on
private actors to execute their every day functions of policy making
and implementation warrants attention as well. Among other things,
private contractors remain relatively unencumbered by the conflict of
interest and other ethical rules that apply to civil servants.
62
A. Objections to Contracting Out
1. Consequentialist Concerns
Typically, one’s enthusiasm for contracting out turns on a host of
considerations, most of which could fairly be labeled “consequential-
ist” because they are motivated solely by a concern about the results
of contracting out,
63
rather than whether contracting out conforms to
a set of a priori principles of “moral” action.
64
That is, the objection to
contracting out would disappear if it were possible to ensure favor-
able results, such as cost savings without a concomitant decline in
quality.
60. See Daniel Guttman, Public Purpose and Private Service: The Twentieth Century
Culture of Contracting Out and the Evolving Law of Diffused Sovereignty, 52 ADMIN. L.
REV. 859, 863 (2000).
61. See id. at 875-76.
62. See id. at 894-95.
63. Consequentialism is the moral theory which holds that the rightness or wrong-
ness of an action depends exclusively on the consequences generated by that action. See
Sharon Dolovich, The Ethics of Private Prisons 75 (Nov. 1999) (unpublished manuscript,
on file with the Florida State University Law Review) (citing Bernard Williams, A Critique
of Utilitarianism, in J.J.C. SMART & BERNARD WILLIAMS, UTILITARIANISM: FOR AND
AGAINST 79 (1973) (describing consequentialism as a form of utilitarianism)).
64. See id. at 72-73 (distinguishing between consequentialist and deontological theo-
ries of moral action).
170 FLORIDA STATE UNIVERSITY LAW REVIEW [Vol. 28:155
In fact, for the most part, scholars do not question the legitimacy
or “morality” of private service provision. Rather, the key question is
whether privatization can deliver on its promised efficiency gains
without sacrificing quality service. As a result, scholars are prone to
note the host of factorsgeographic, demographic, and economic
that can thwart efforts to achieve efficiency gains through contract-
ing out. These include such problems as an absence of competition, a
lack of opportunities for cost savings, or the small size of a market.
65
In some cases, the task that government wishes to contract out may
be too difficult to specify in a contract and, therefore, difficult to
monitor. Because the case for privatization has sounded largely in
the language of cost savings and, to some extent increased effective-
ness, demonstrating whether these gains will in fact obtain has be-
come both politically and practically important to the privatization
movement. Those who support privatization on such instrumental,
rather than ideological, grounds are advocates of what one scholar
calls “pragmatic privatization.”
66
Thus, opposition to contracting out may stem from worry about
results alone, which is ultimately an empirical question. For exam-
ple, one might oppose privatizing welfare benefits on the theory that
it will not cut costs and might result in the “creaming” or “churning”
of welfare recipients to limit the numbers of claimants.
67
Similarly,
one might oppose prison privatization on the theory that it will fail to
ameliorate overcrowding and might in fact swell the prison popula-
tion due to the incentives that private contractors face to maintain
high numbers of inmates.
In a results-oriented framework, then, we would want to ensure
that contracting out in fact produces the positive benefits we desire
without producing the negative effects we seek to avoid. In the con-
text of prison privatization, for example, we would prize cost savings
and bureaucratic efficiency, and perhaps even superior performance
in rehabilitation and recidivism, but we would fear degraded prison
conditions and increased threats to inmate security. Assessing any
one instance of contracting out requires that we pay attention to con-
text: we would want to know more about the potential for efficiency
gains and more about the trade-offs.
2. “Technocratic” Concerns
To some extent, objections to contracting out might be ameliorated
by careful attention to contract design. Contracts could specify tasks
65. See Deller, supra note 45, at 149-50.
66. Harvey B. Feigenbaum & Jeffrey R. Henig, The Political Underpinnings of
Privatization: A Typology, 46 WORLD POL. 185, 193-94 (1994).
67. For definitions of creaming and churning, see Kennedy, supra note 31, at 241-47.
2000] CONTRACTING STATE 171
more clearly, detail procedures more thoroughly, and clarify respon-
sibilities. Certainly, many public-private contracts suffer from these
“technocratic” weaknesses. However, there is a limit to technocratic
solutions. No matter how careful the drafter, some tasks are difficult
to specify in contractual terms (for example, delivering quality health
care or providing a safe environment for prisoners).
68
For many im-
portant services and functions contractual incompleteness is inevita-
ble.
69
No contract can be specific enough to anticipate any and all
situations that a private provider might encounter. Instead, the con-
tract becomes a framework and a set of default rules that will help
direct future gap filling.
70
In fact, contractual vagueness may be de-
sirable in some circumstances, as, for example, when the parties are
familiar with each other, have been repeat players, and have estab-
lished trust.
71
Even so, vagueness may impede meaningful monitor-
ing.
For those functions that are easier to specify, agencies may be
nonetheless ill-equipped to monitor performance, whether because of
68. A GAO report studied six governments’ (five states’ and one city’s) experiences
with privatization. Government officials reported that contract monitoring is key and con-
sists of both contract auditing, which ensures that contractors are paid and contract obli-
gations are met, and technical or performance monitoring, which ensures that the contrac-
tors meet the quantity and quality terms of the contract. Generally, performance monitor-
ing is more difficult than contract auditing for several reasons. Government employees
need training in order to perform sophisticated analysis and monitoring. Contract re-
quirements need to be precise to allow effective monitoring. Whether a service’s obje ctives
could be defined easily and measured for monitoring purposes factored into some states’
decisions to privatize the service. Also, all the state government officials noted that per-
formance monitoring is the weakest link in their privatization activities. See GENERAL
ACCOUNTING OFFICE, GAO/GGD-97-48, PRIVATIZATION: LESSONS LEARNED BY STATE AND
LOCAL GOVERNMENTS 17 (1997), http://www.access.gpo.gov/su_docs/aces/aces160.shtml.
69. Even procurement contracts can be incomplete and vague, and although design
specifications might change, for the most part, in the procurement context government is
buying a definable product (an F-15, for example). On the frequency with which “construc-
tive change” orders have historically been issued by government personnel supervising
procurement contracts, see F. Trowbridge vom Baur, Differences Between Commercial Con-
tracts and Government Contracts, 53 A.B.A. J. 247, 250 (1967).
70. See Robert E. Scott, Conflict and Cooperation in Long-Term Contracts, 75 CAL. L.
REV. 2005, 2024-25 (1987) (arguing that parties to long-term contracts negotiate adjust-
ments to formal terms in order to adjust to changing conditions over the life of the con-
tract), cited in William E. Kovacic, Law, Economics, and the Reinvention of Public Admini-
stration: Using Relational Agreements to Reduce the Cost of Procurement Regulation and
Other Forms of Government Intervention in the Economy, 50 ADMIN L. REV. 141, 148 n.25
(1998). For additional scholarship on the development of informal norms within formal
contractual regimes, see generally Lisa Bernstein, Merchant Law in a Merchant Court: Re-
thinking the Code’s Search for Immanent Business Norms, 144 U. PA. L. REV. 1765 (1996).
This more recent work on social norms builds on a much older scholarship in the law and
society tradition devoted to describing the relational dimensions of contractual regimes.
See, e.g., Stewart MacCauley, Non-Contractual Relations in Business: A Preliminary
Study, 28 AM. SOC. REV. 55 (1963).
71. See John T. Scholz, Cooperative Regulatory Enforcement and the Politics of Ad-
ministrative Effectiveness, 85 AM. POL. SCI. REV. 115, 132 (1991) (reflecting on the condi-
tions most conducive to flexible and cooperative enforcement strategies).
172 FLORIDA STATE UNIVERSITY LAW REVIEW [Vol. 28:155
resource constraints or a lack of familiarity with contract manage-
ment. Weak monitoring in turn makes it difficult to discern whether
contracting out is producing the desired results. Of course, some of
these problems are related. Government agencies may monitor in-
adequately because the task described in the contract itself eludes
definition. They might be unrelated, however. Agency staff may
monitor poorly because of an absence of training, because their in-
centives direct them toward other priorities, or because they are cor-
rupt.
3. Ethical Concerns
More fundamentally, one might object to contracting out certain
functions on moral grounds. Many people have a viscerally negative
reaction to the idea that some government functionsthose they
view as symbolically important or inherently governmentalmight
be contracted out to private parties, notwithstanding the possibility
that private actors may perform those functions more cost-effectively.
Some draw the line at what they call “core” governmental func-
tionsthose believed to be at the heart of sovereignty, such as for-
eign affairs, tax collection, national defense, and policing, for exam-
ple.
72
For them, the distinction turns on the belief that certain func-
tions are traditionally the obligation of the state.
73
The same impetus
to reserve “core” functions to the state motivates the desire to keep
the heart of regulatory power in the hands of government, thus al-
lowing implementation, but not policy making, to be contracted out.
While there might be widespread agreement that a few functions
(such as national defense) ought to be both financed and performed
by the state, choosing where to draw the line between these and
other nonessential or peripheral functions, and the reasons for draw-
ing the line, remains a matter of debate. Different people would no
doubt consider different functions to be the inherent responsibility of
the sovereign; in addition to the four examples listed above, educa-
72. See, e.g., Oliver E. Williamson, Public and Private Bureaucracies: A Transaction
Cost Economics Perspective, 15 J.L. ECON. & ORG. 306, 322-24 (1998) (explaining why for-
eign affairs ought not to be privatized by focusing on the vague consideration of “probity”
rather than “hold-up” and other transaction cost problems).
73. In fact, most so -called public functions are neither traditionally nor self-evidently
inherently governmental. Private prisons predated public ones. Private police predated the
public police. See David A. Sklansky, The Private Police, 46 UCLA L. REV. 1165, 1198-2000
(1999). Private charitable organizations predated the social insurance schemes of the New
Deal. Nonetheless, some commentators believe that certain functions ought to be reserved
to the state because of their moral and symbolic importance. See PRIVATE PRISONS AND THE
PUBLIC INTEREST 155, 173, 176 (Douglas C. McDonald ed., 1990) (arguing that some func-
tions, such as the incarceration function, are so inherently public that it is immoral to pri-
vatize them). For an argument that the market is not an appropriate mechanism for pro-
ducing and distributing collective goods such as education and health care, see MICHAEL
WALZER, SPHERES OF JUSTICE: A DEFENSE OF PLURALISM AND EQUALITY 86, 198 (1983).
2000] CONTRACTING STATE 173
tion, civil and criminal adjudication, and even transportation plausi-
bly merit inclusion in the “core” category.
Some commentators object to prison privatization on these
grounds, arguing that criminal punishment, an expression of soci-
ety’s moral condemnation, is a core state functionthe kind of judg-
ment that, in a democratic society, ought to be imposed by the state.
In this vein, John DiIulio argues that incarceration is part of the
state’s inalienable “duty to govern.”
74
Sharon Dolovich similarly
frames her objection to privatization in “expressivist” terms, claiming
that prison privatization sends the wrong message about the values
of a “liberal ethical society.”
75
Whether we label such objections symbolic, ethical, traditionalist,
deontological, or expressivist, the simple notion behind all of them is
that contracting out certain functions is somehow corrosive of democ-
ratic values. Absent a strong grounding in moral theory, these objec-
tions can sound vague, tautological, and decidedly nonempirical,
76
es-
pecially compared to the hard-nosed efficiency arguments of privati-
zation advocates, but they are real and pervasive.
77
Many people
simply distinguish intuitively between those services and functions
that might tolerably be assigned to private parties and those they be-
lieve ought to be performed by government. An individual who cares
little about whether her household garbage is collected by the city of
New York or Acme Waste Corporation may feel quite differently
about the identity of a prison guard or a police officer.
78
On this score, the potential for coercion is an important considera-
tion in whether we view contracting out as legitimate, and it merits
singling out. Some functions allocate burdens as opposed to benefits.
Commentators may believe that when people are forced by the state
to suffer a burden, contracting out is particularly inappropriate, and
that administering coercion in particular ought to be the job of the
state. Because burdens can implicate civil liberties, safeguards on
the exercise of authority and accountability are all the more impor-
tant. Thus, when government contracts out the power to punish, just
74. John J. DiIulio, Jr., The Duty to Govern: A Critical Perspective on the Private
Management of Prisons and Jails, in PRIVATE PRISONS AND THE PUBLIC INTEREST, supra
note 73, at 173.
75. Dolovich, supra note 63, at 76.
76. Most functions that seem traditionally governmental, including tax collection, po-
licing, and incarceration, were at one time or another performed by private individuals or
organizations. See DONAHUE, supra note 2, at 34 (commenting on the “tax farmers” of an-
cient Rome and the historical proliferation of mercenary armies). To say that a function is
“traditionally” or “inherently” governmental still requires an argument.
77. See, e.g., John J. DiIulio, Jr., What’s Wrong with Private Prisons, 92 PUB.
INTEREST 61, 70-71 (1988); Dolovich, supra note 63, at 71 (articulating an “expressivist”
critique of prison privatization that goes beyond “consequentialist” arguments about cost
and quality).
78. On the history of private policing, see Sklansky, supra note 73, at 1165.
174 FLORIDA STATE UNIVERSITY LAW REVIEW [Vol. 28:155
as when it delegates its coercive regulatory authority, we might
worry more than when government contracts out responsibility for
conferring benefits, such as publicly financed health care, education,
or job training.
Consider, again, the difference between contracting out waste col-
lection and prison operation. Although everyone has an interest in
the proper collection of waste (particularly given the environmental
and human health risks posed by improper collection, transportation,
and disposal), this activity seems not to implicate civil liberties. We
simply do not experience the waste collection function as coercive.
For the most part, then, whether waste collection and services like it
ought to be provided by government or private actors appears to be
less a normative question and more a question of which institution
can do a better job for less money. For a large percentage of services
and functions then, we are more likely to ask the type of questions
characteristic of the “pragmatic” view of privatization: Will the con-
tractual regime be adequately competitive to ensure cost savings and
high quality? Will the bidding process be corrupt? With this kind of
function, the only relevant normative question might be whether the
community is willing to trade labor losses for more efficient service.
79
Realistically, however, there are few activities with as much po-
tential for coercion as incarceration. Few social services or functions
funded by government but provided by private parties raise as much
alarm over civil liberties, even if they affect important interests. In-
deed, incarceration is unique. As a society, we are still considering
whether to proceed with the experiments in private prison manage-
ment, and at least with this particular function, the federal and state
governments might still turn back. By contrast, there is little chance
of retreating from the private delivery of most social services. The
public-private networks necessary to accomplish “public” ends have
been developing for at least half a century, and they appear well en-
trenched. In any event, there appears in the United States (and in-
deed worldwide) to be little public appetite for relying directly on
government itself to deliver most social services. In an era marked by
antipathy toward government bureaucracy, neither technocratic nor
ethical objections are likely to deter the trend toward contracting out.
4. Administrative Law Concerns
For the most part, I have argued, economists and public manage-
ment scholars engaged in the privatization debates focus on the con-
79. See Graham & Prosser, supra note 36, at 63 (noting that severe job losses have co-
incided with privatization but falling short of arguing causation). Anticipating job losses or
less favorable work conditions, public service employees unions raise the strongest obje c-
tions to such privatization schemes. See id.
2000] CONTRACTING STATE 175
ditions under which private provision will offer greater efficiency
than direct government provision. The goal of this results-oriented
inquiry is to identify the economic conditions that might obstruct
government efforts to structure privatization most effectively.
80
In
this view, technocratic problems of contract design are thought to be
fairly and easily solved with more careful drafting and greater speci-
ficity. Accountability arises, if at all, as one of these technocratic
problems that might be addressed by a tweak of drafting and design;
formal agency oversight usually suffices for accountability.
81
However, contracting out presents serious and complicated ques-
tions about the rationality, public participation, openness, and ac-
countability of publicly funded and privately conferred services
concerns that are likely to be important to administrative law schol-
ars and not easily assuaged.
82
From an administrative law perspec-
tive, then, we would ask different questions: whether contracts for
social service delivery are produced in a fair and open manner with
sufficient public input, and whether they afford procedural protec-
tions, including private rights of action, to third-party beneficiaries.
In addition, we might inquire into the potential conflict between pub-
lic law norms of deference to agencies and private law principles of
contract interpretation when it comes to adjudicating disputes.
83
Contracting out raises a version of the principal-agent problem
that arises whenever legislatures delegate decisionmaking authority
to public bureaucracies. Because third-party beneficiaries (and the
general public) are one step further removed from the private pro-
vider than from the agency, however, the possibility of meaningful
public oversight becomes increasingly remote. The obstacles to third
party vindication seem particularly objectionable from an adminis-
80. See Oliver Hart et al., The Proper Scope of Government: Theory and an Applica-
tion to Prisons, 112 Q.J. ECON. 1127, 1129 (1997) (defining the fundamental difference be-
tween public and private ownership as the allocation of residual control rights to approve
changes in uncontracted-for contingencies, and evincing a concern with the trade -off be-
tween cost and quality).
81. See, e.g., Ira P. Robbins, The Impact of the Delegation Doctrine on Prison Privati-
zation, 35 UCLA L. REV. 911 (1988).
82. See DONAHUE, supra note 2, at 83.
83. Historically, administrative law concerns have played a relatively minor role in
debates over contracting out. Occasionally, commentators will advocate protecting the due
process rights of the contractors, who fear arbitrary decisionmaking by the government in
the contract award and management process. In the same vein, recipients of discretionary
government grants have sometimes argued for a more formalized decisionmaking process
and suggested that discretionary awards ought to be subject to judicial review. Until the
recent clamor for patients’ bills of rights in the context of health care delivery, however,
the interests of the third-party beneficiaries in public-private contracts, the manner in
which government negotiated the terms of those contracts with private contractors, and
the potential incompatibility of private contract law principles with public law principles of
deference to agency interpretations seemed decidedly secondary.
176 FLORIDA STATE UNIVERSITY LAW REVIEW [Vol. 28:155
trative law perspective because the government appears to insulate
itself from accountability by relying on private providers.
The constitutional constraints and elaborate procedural rules that
govern agency decisionmaking only infrequently apply to private de-
cisionmaking undertaken pursuant to public-private contract. Proce-
dural rules, such as the requirement of notice and comment prior to
the promulgation of a rule, provide points of entry for members of the
public affected by the regulation and grounds to challenge ensuing
policy choices. However, analogous opportunities for public access
appear to be absent in the contracting process. For example, public-
private contracts for health care delivery often incorporate statutory
and regulatory requirements, making those requirements enforce-
able as contractual terms. Through the incorporation of regulation
into contract, Medicaid contracts for health care delivery can func-
tion as a means of standard setting. And yet the contracting process
lacks the procedural safeguards that characterize traditional notice-
and-comment rulemaking.
Once contracts take effect, moreover, beneficiaries enjoy few pro-
cedural rights to challenge decisionmaking that affects their inter-
ests. Although courts might imply third-party beneficiary rights into
contracts, the documents themselves almost never explicitly afford
beneficiaries the right to sue. The absence of public participation or
third-party rights of enforcement are particularly notable in light of
the risk of ineffective agency oversight. Even when agencies have at
their disposal the means to constrain private discretion, imposing
constraints may be unappealing for political reasons or practically in-
feasible.
These issues arise even more strikingly when governments con-
tract for especially controversial functions, such as private prison
management.
84
Contracts between private prisons and state agencies
can be highly detailed and specific, and in many respects (for exam-
ple, the issuing of requests for proposals and the competitive bidding
process) they conform to the traditional procurement model. At the
same time, because of the unique service for which government is
contracting, the need for such contracts to provide accountability is
acute.
a. Examples.To illustrate the administrative law concerns that
arise when states contract out social services or important functions,
I draw on three examples of contracting that I have developed in
84. Although only 3% of the prison population has been privatizedand although
most of these are either juvenile facilities, INS detention centers, or low security facili-
tiesthere is a marked trend toward prison privatization in many states. See Hart et al.,
supra note 80, at 1147, 1154.
2000] CONTRACTING STATE 177
greater detail elsewhere: nursing homes, the federal Medicaid pro-
gram, and private prisons.
85
i. Nursing Homes.Consider, for example, the mechanism by
which the federal government funds the provision of health care to
Medicaid patients in private nursing homes.
86
Under the federal
Medicaid program, the federal government reimburses states for
Medicaid-eligible patient care. Medicaid funding overwhelmingly
supports the private nursing home industry, subsidizing capital and
operating expenditures and reimbursing more than sixty percent of
eligible patient care.
87
To qualify for participation in the federal pro-
gram, states must comply with a complicated body of federal law and
regulation. States in turn rely on a combination of licensing, regula-
tion, and contract to impose obligations on the private nursing homes
that deliver the care.
88
Thus, private homes cannot collect reim-
bursement from the state unless they comply with a state-provider
agreement (a public-private contract) governing care delivery.
89
Although private nursing homes are arguably the most heavily
regulated of all health care delivery institutions in the United
States,
90
these public-private contracts still raise significant adminis-
85. See Freeman, supra note 3, at 598, 625.
86. Nursing homes are populated by residents whose care is paid for differently: some
through Medicaid, others through Medicare, and still others through private insurance. In
this example, however, I discuss only Medicaid patients.
87. See Butler, supra note 26, at 1318 (claiming that, at time of the article, Medicaid
paid more than half of total nursing home revenues).
88. See Maureen Armour, A Nursing Home’s Good Faith Duty “to” Care: Redefining a
Fragile Relationship Using the Law of Contract, 39 ST. LOUIS U. L.J. 217, 223 (1994) (re-
ferring to the Texas process whereby the state regulatory agency determines homes quali-
fied to participate in Medicaid and enters into contract with them for provision of services);
see also Butler, supra note 26, at 1322-27.
89. See Butler, supra note 26, at 1322-27.
90. When Congress passed the Omnibus Balanced Budget Reconciliation Act of 1987
(OBBRA), Pub. L. No. 100-203, 101 Stat. 1330 (codified as amended in scattered sections of
42 U.S.C.), it established detailed statutory standards governing the quality of care in
nursing homes. See § 4211, 101 Stat. at 1330-182 to 1330-208. Among other things, the
OBBRA redefined the required quality of care to include an effective component reflecting
patients’ quality of life and adopted a “Patients’ ‘Bill of Rights.’” See 42 U.S.C. § 1395i-3(c)
(1994). The statutory standards are quite detailed and reflect a crackdown on substandard
care in nursing homes since the inception of Medicaid and Medicare in the 1960s. States
enforce the new federal standards, elaborated in Department of Health and Human Ser-
vices (HHS) regulations by regulating and licensing nursing facilities within their jurisdic-
tions, predominantly relying on a state-administered survey and inspection process to en-
sure compliance. By comparison with hospitals, for example, nursing homes are more
closely and directly regulated by state agencies. With respect to nursing home care, the
Health Care Financing Administration (HCFA) exerts relatively stringent oversight. For
example, HCFA posts nursing home survey results on the web. Compare Health Care Fin.
Admin., Nursing Home Database, at http://www.medicare.gov/NHCompare/home.asp (vis-
ited Apr. 4, 2000) (providing search system to compare state ratings of different nursing
homes), with DEPARTMENT OF HEALTH AND HUMAN SERVS., THE EXTERNAL REVIEW OF
HOSPITAL QUALITY: A CALL FOR GREATER ACCOUNTABILITY (July 1999), at
http://www.dhhs.gov/progorg/oei/reports/a381.pdf, and DEPARTMENT OF HEALTH AND
HUMAN SERVS., THE EXTERNAL REVIEW OF HOSPITAL QUALITY: THE ROLE OF
178 FLORIDA STATE UNIVERSITY LAW REVIEW [Vol. 28:155
trative law concerns. First, private litigants enjoy “no rights or pro-
tectable expectations” regarding the care they receive from nursing
homes.
91
That is, despite extensive federal and state regulation, nurs-
ing homes are not considered “public” providers of health care.
92
Thus, private denials of care and private eviction determinations do
not constitute state action, eliminating constitutional due process
claims as a mechanism of oversight.
93
Second, nursing home residents face significant obstacles to en-
forcing contractual terms as third-party beneficiaries.
94
Courts only
reluctantly find state-provider contracts to be a source of third-party
beneficiary claims against nursing homes for statutory violations.
95
While nursing home residents might argue that the federal Medicaid
statute creates an implied private right of action, as a general mat-
ter, courts rarely recognize private rights of action to redress viola-
tions of federal law.
96
As with third-party beneficiary claims, to the
extent that courts have recognized implied rights of action, they have
done so to enforce “specially iterated rights” stipulated in legislation,
such as those covering wrongful transfer or eviction decisions by the
ACCREDITATION (July 1999), at http://www.dhhs.gov/progorg/oei/reports/a382.pdf (detailing
lack of accountability and quality oversight in accredited hospitals).
91. Armour, supra note 88, at 254 (noting that providers’ lack of duty beyond the
regulatory structure limits patients’ private right of action).
92. See Fuzie v. Manor Care, Inc., 461 F. Supp. 689, 695 (N.D. Ohio 1977).
93. Federal courts have, on occasion, held private providers to be state actors when
they are the only providers of care in a government-regulated arrangement and where they
therefore assume responsibility for the state’s mandated health care duties. See Catanzano
v. Dowling, 60 F.3d 113, 120 (2d Cir. 1995) (holding state-certified home health agency de-
terminations regarding medical necessity of home health care to be state action since only
certified home health agencies can provide care to Medicaid beneficiaries); J.K. v. Dillen-
berg, 836 F. Supp. 694, 698-99 (D. Ariz. 1993) (holding that private regional behavioral
health authorities were state actors where they were the sole providers of the state’s Medi-
caid behavioral health services for children).
94. See Anthony Jon Waters, The Property in the Promise: A Study of the Third Party
Beneficiary Rule, 98 HARV. L. REV. 1109, 1174-78 (1985) (describing some federal courts’
holdings that third-party beneficiaries have no private right of action on the contract
where the claim is traditionally relegated to state law); cf. Martinez v. Socoma, 521 P.2d
841, 849 (1974) (denying unemployed residents’ claim as third-party beneficiaries to fed-
eral training and employment contracts with local corporations because residents were
merely incide ntal beneficiaries of the public purpose behind the contracts).
95. See Fuzie, 461 F. Supp. at 694-95, 697 (holding that a private nursing home was
not a state actor and that the plaintiff had no implied private right of action under Medi-
caid regulations, but finding that the plaintiff-patient did have a claim as a third-party
beneficiary under the contract); see also Wate rs, supra note 94, at 1186-88 (describing
Fuzie as an example of courts using the third-party beneficiary rule to create a private
right to enforce public programs regardless of legislative intent).
96. See Richard B. Stewart & Cass R. Sunstein, Public Programs and Private Rights,
95 HARV. L. REV. 1193, 1302-06 (1982) (arguing that the Supreme Court has created a
strong presumption against judicial recognition of private rights of action). Although some
states have passed legislation affording patients private rights of action, this legislation o f-
ten limits them to such specific rights as eviction rather than general standards of care.
See Armour, supra note 88, at 259-60.
2000] CONTRACTING STATE 179
home.
97
As a result, only patients who are wrongly evicted, but not
those who receive substandard care, would have any chance of suc-
cess using either of these arguments.
Alternatively, residents might seek to enforce the terms of their
own contracts with providers (typically, new residents sign contracts
upon admission to the nursing home). However, absent express con-
tractual representation to the contrary, courts tend to interpret ad-
mission contracts according to tort standards of quality of care,
which usually disfavor residents.
98
Relying on state or federal en-
forcement of provider contract terms may be no more promising for
residents than taking matters into their own hands. Contractual
terms in the state-provider agreements may be vague or agency
monitoring insufficient, due to a long tradition of relatively weak
government oversight.
99
Absent vicarious liability, the contracting
agency may lack sufficient motivation to supervise the provider’s
compliance with the agreement. In fact, governments have histori-
cally taken a more aggressive approach to negotiating and monitor-
ing procurement contracts than they have with regard to contracts
governing the delivery of benefits.
100
Even when an agency is armed with a detailed contract and a va-
riety of enforcement tools, however, its interest in the operation of
the contractual regime may not (and often will not) coincide with
that of the ultimate consumer.
101
An agency may care more about
cost savings and blame shifting than quality of service,
102
or it may be
97. See Armour, supra note 88, at 259-60.
98. See id. at 266-70 (summarizing standard critiques of the tort paradigm’s applica-
tion in the nursing home context).
99. Historically, governments have purchased services like health care differently
than they have procured goods such as airplanes. See BRUCE C. VLADECK, UNLOVING
CARE: THE NURSING HOME TRAGEDY 98-99 (1980).
100. For example, procurement contracts obligate suppliers to meet specific perform-
ance standards, whereas until recent years, state provider agreements rarely contained ei-
ther performance standards or penalties for nonfulfillment. See id. at 98 (arguing that in
the 1970s there was “no comparison between a typical government procurement contract
and a typical ‘provider agreement’ between a state Medicaid agency and a nursing home”).
While in theory the nursing home is required to meet all the requirements of the state’s li-
censing and health codes, “the separation of the enforcement from the purchasing function
seriously limits [the codes’] enforceability.” Id. at 99. On the weaknesses of reimbursement
as a quality assurance tool when the Medicaid agency is not the licensing certification
agency, see Butler, supra note 26, at 1329. Inattention to contracting details flowed from
Medicaid’s roots as a redistributive claims processing operation.
101. There is nothing about the divergence of agency and Medicaid beneficiary inter-
ests that is unique to managed care. As an outgrowth of welfare cash assistance programs,
Medicaid has always had a “corporate culture” of saving money and preventing fraud. His-
torically, insurance programs like Medicaid have had no responsibility for the health of
beneficiaries. I thank Elizabeth Wehr for helpful comments on this point.
102. See James W. Fossett, Managed Care and Devolution, in MEDICAID AND
DEVOLUTION, supra note 27, at 106, 120 (“The major continued political appeal of managed
care rests on its perceived ability to produce budget savings while shifting financial risk
and political blame for spending reductions to private agencies.”).
180 FLORIDA STATE UNIVERSITY LAW REVIEW [Vol. 28:155
more interested in maintaining smooth relationships with its con-
tractual partners over the long term than in individual fairness or
responsiveness to consumers in the short term. Even a well-meaning
agency may be torn between competing goals. The price of closer
scrutiny over private providers of care could prove to be the flexibil-
ity, cost savings, and innovative capacity associated with relying on
private providers in the first placea trade-off that some agencies
may not be willing to make.
ii. Medicaid and Managed Care.Beyond the nursing home en-
vironment, the Medicaid program offers another useful example of
how public-private contracting to deliver social services is fraught
with accountability problems. To obtain health care for Medicaid re-
cipients, state Medicaid agencies purchase care from a range of pro-
viders. In recent years, state agencies have shifted from employing a
fee-for-service system to purchasing care for Medicaid beneficiaries
from Managed Care Organizations (MCOs).
103
As a result, states in-
creasingly require Medicaid beneficiaries to choose among the MCOs
offered by the state, much like employees in firms might choose from
a menu of managed care providers offered by their employers. The
Balanced Budget Act of 1997
104
explicitly authorizes this practice by
eliminating the prior requirement of a federal waiver for mandatory
enrollment of Medicaid beneficiaries in managed care.
105
Thus, states
can now require Medicaid beneficiaries to enroll in managed care
plans from which they may disenroll only “for cause” or at prescribed
times.
Moreover, devolution of decisionmaking authoritya phenomenon
that has coincided with the trend toward contracting out and which
has specifically occurred in the Medicaid regimecan exacerbate
monitoring problems associated with contractual relationships by
adding the need for greater intergovernmental monitoring to gov-
ernment-provider monitoring. In addition, as mentioned above, devo-
103. See John T. Boese, When Angry Patients Become Angry Prosecutors: Medical Ne-
cessity Determinations, Quality of Care and the Qui Tam Law, 43 ST. LOUIS U. L.J. 53, 56
(1999) (reporting that nearly 17% of Medicare patients are enrolled in managed care pro-
grams). In a fee-for-service system, consumers of health services rely on their physicians to
determine the care they need and insurance companies compensate providers based on the
volume and type of services provided. In theory, managed care responds to the tendency to
overconsume health care by requiring primary care physicians with no financial stake in
overtreatment to perform a “gatekeeping” function in determining the care required. See
id. at 58-60.
104. Pub. L. No. 105-33, §§ 4001-4002, 111 Stat. 251, 275-327 (codified as amended at
42 U.S.C. § 1395w -21 (West Supp. 2000)) (enacting “Medicare+Choice” program).
105. See § 4702, 111 Stat. at 494 (codified at 42 U.S.C. § 1396d(a)(25), (t) (Supp. V
1999)). Federal Medicaid law has always permitted states to purchase managed care se r-
vices for Medicaid beneficiaries who enroll on a voluntary basis. Most of the mandatory
Medicaid managed care programs currently operate under one of two types of waivers au-
thorized by section 1115 of the Social Security Act. See 42 U.S.C. § 1315(a) (1994)
(amended 1996).
2000] CONTRACTING STATE 181
lution can lead to significant dependence on private actors to deliver
services for which states and localities find themselves newly respon-
sible, or it can intensify a dependent relationship that already ex-
ists.
106
For example, the federal block grants that have replaced the enti-
tlement to federal financial assistance for the poor in the Personal
Responsibility and Work Opportunity and Reconciliation Act of
1996
107
(PRWORA) allow states, with few conditions, to design benefit
programs and eligibility requirements for welfare recipients.
108
As a
result, the Act will likely accelerate the existing trend toward greater
reliance on nongovernmental actors.
109
The PRWORA specifically al-
lows states to operate welfare programs “through contracts with
charitable, religious, or private organizations.”
110
Nongovernmental
106. See Kennedy, supra note 31, at 231 (describing Personal Responsibility and Work
Opportunity Reconciliation Act of 1996 (PRA) as permitting states to use private corpora-
tions to operate benefit programs). For a detailed description of the Temporary Assistance
to Needy Families block grant (which replaced Aid to Families with Dependant Children
(AFDC)) and the Child Care and Development block grant, see Mark Greenberg, Welfare
Restructuring and Working Poor Family Policy: The New Context, in HARD LABOR: WOMEN
AND WORK IN THE POST-WELFARE ERA 24, 33-34 (Joel F. Handler & Lucie White eds.,
1999). Under the prior AFDC regime, states were obligated to provide benefits to individu-
als eligible under federal law. See id. at 25.
107. Pub. L. No. 104-193, § 1330, 110 Stat. 2105 (1996).
108. Pursuant to the PRWORA, states now determine for themselves which popula-
tions to serve and exercise very broad discretion in spending block grants, provided that
they do so in a manner designed to accomplish the permissible purposes specified in the
Act, such as providing assistance to needy families. See Greenberg, supra note 106, at 31.
109. The new balance of power between state and federal governments under the
PRWORA has attracted considerable attention, but the reallocation of authority from
states to private corporations as a result of welfare reform may be more significant than
the new balance of authority between the federal and state governments. See Kennedy, su-
pra note 31, at 232 (suggesting that the federal-state balance might return to federal
dominance but that auth ority ceded to the private sector will be harder to regain). Under
the law, the state has no obligation to provide assistance for low-income families. See
Greenberg, supra note 106, at 31. A state wishing to do so has considerable flexibility. It
could provide assistance through cash or noncash means or fund social services rather
than providing other forms of assistance. See id. A state could also “turn over some or vir-
tually all funding to nonprofit organizations, religious groups, or for-profit organizations
for an array of different approaches.” Id. at 37. Prior to passage of the PRWORA, many
states were already experimenting with time limits, work requirements and, most impo r-
tantly for our purposes, “privatizing” aspects of their welfare systems; the federal govern-
ment had routinely granted states waivers under the AFDC program in order to allow
them flexibility in administering benefits. See id. at 25-28 (describing state initiatives as a
mixture of expansion and contraction of program eligibility). For a critical view, see Lucy
A. Williams, The Abuse of Section 1115 Waivers: Welfare Reform in Search of a Standard,
12 YALE L. & POLY REV. 8 (1994) (arguing that unrestricted state discretion is an inappro-
priate strategy for addressing welfare policy concerns).
110. Pub. L. No. 104-193, § 104, 110 Stat. at 2161. Major corporations anticipating a
significant role in welfare administration not only lobbied in support of the legislation but
also rushed to capitalize on it. See Kennedy, supra note 31, at 258-59.
182 FLORIDA STATE UNIVERSITY LAW REVIEW [Vol. 28:155
organizations increasingly will deliver benefits, exercising the con-
siderable discretion that “administration” and “delivery” imply.
111
Of course, welfare reform represents a wholesale devolution of au-
thority that dwarfs the more modest devolution exemplified by the
Medicaid regime, but both examples illustrate how devolution can
indirectly empower nongovernment decision makers to make impor-
tant policy determinations that go far beyond the mere implementa-
tion of government directives. Devolution in the Medicaid context not
only increases reliance on private health care institutions, it also in-
directly increases state government dependence on private accredita-
tion bodies such as the National Committee on Quality Assurance
(NCQA) to certify that private health care delivery organizations (in-
cluding MCOs) meet adequate standards of care.
112
Until recently,
NCQA certification was primarily voluntaryit offered MCOs an ad-
vantage when competing for lucrative health care delivery contracts.
However, when states became managed care purchasers, they
adopted the benchmark of quality for managed care endorsed by
111. Critics worry that private firms administering welfare benefits will maximize
profits by “churning” and “creaming” recipients, effectively making policy decisions about
who will receive benefits. “Churning” refers to the variety of burdensome administrative
procedures used to dissuade potential beneficiaries from applying for benefits, including
requiring applicants to comply with extremely complicated verification and documentation
requirements, subjecting them to interminable waits, and locating facilities in inconven-
ient locations. See Kennedy, supra note 31, at 241-47. “Creaming” refers to finding the best
qualified beneficiaries jobs while allowing the bulk of beneficiaries to languish and eventu-
ally be dropped from the rolls. See id. at 263.
112. The NCQA is a private, nonprofit organization that assesses and accredits health
plans. It is governed by a board of directors consisting of employers, consumer and labor
representatives, health plans, quality experts, policy makers, and representatives from or-
ganized medicine. See NCQA, National Committee for Quality Assurance: An Overview, at
http://www.ncqa.org/Pages/about/overview3.htm (visited Apr. 4, 2000); see also 1 SARA
ROSENBAUM ET AL., GEORGE WASHINGTON UNIV. MED. CTR., NEGOTIATING THE NEW
HEALTH SYSTEM: A NATIONWIDE STUDY OF MEDICAID MANAGED CARE CONTRACTS (Kay A.
Johnson ed., 2d ed. 1998) [hereinafter NEGOTIATING THE NEW HEALTH SYSTEM] (noting
that “state Medicaid agencies, like other purchasers, elect to rely on managed care organi-
zations to conduct their own quality assessment and improvement efforts, as well as (in-
creasingly) on the industry accreditation process”), http://www.gwumc.edu/chrp/overview/
overview.htm (last visited Oct. 23, 2000). As MCOs proliferate, the accreditation process
for health plans becomes more competitive. Competitors of NCQA are the Joint Commis-
sion on Accreditation of Healthcare Organizations (JCAHO), the Accreditation Association
for Ambulatory Health Care, the Foundation for Accountability, the Medical Quality
Commission, and the Utilization Review Accreditation Commission. See John K. Iglehart,
The National Committee for Quality Assurance, 335 NEW ENG . J. MED. 995, 998 (1996).
Further, although the MCO accreditation program is voluntary and rigorous, it has been
well received by the managed care industry, and almost half the HMOs in the nation, cov-
ering three quarters of all HMO enrollees, are currently involved in the NCQA accredita-
tion process. For an organization to become accredited by NCQA, it must undergo a survey
and meet certain standards designed to evaluate the health plan’s clinical and administra-
tive systems. In particular, NCQA’s accreditation surveys look at a health plan’s efforts to
continuously improve the quality of care and service it delivers. One measure of the value
of accreditation is the growing list of employers who require or request NCQA accredita-
tion of the plans they do business with. See NCQA, supra.
2000] CONTRACTING STATE 183
commercial purchasers, which was, at the time, private accredita-
tion.
113
From an administrative law perspective, managed care contracts
between state agencies and MCOs raise serious questions about fair-
ness and access for beneficiaries. Through contract, the parties in-
corporate existing federal and state standards and agree to terms
under which states will consider them satisfied. Unlike traditional
rulemaking, however, contract negotiation does not afford either the
general public or Medicaid beneficiaries a role in decisionmaking.
Negotiating contracts against the backdrop of elaborate federal
regulations also introduces considerable risks for the state agency
which translate into accountability concerns for the public. As a re-
cent report describes, “[S]tandard setting through contracts holds
unprecedented enforceability implications, because of the legal con-
sequences of drafting error or omission on the agency’s part.”
114
Should states carelessly draft state-provider contracts, they could
find themselves directly responsible for services and benefits that
they intend to pass on to private MCOs.
115
Agencies may nonetheless
prefer contractual instruments because they are procedurally easier
to manage than direct regulation of health care delivery through the
traditional rulemaking process alone, even when this managerial
benefit may come at the expense of public participation.
In addition, public-private contracts might compromise the defer-
ence agencies normally receive when they act in their regulatory ca-
pacity. Although administrative law principles suggest that courts
should defer to an agency’s subsequent interpretation of its publicly
promulgated rules, courts may interpret contracts according to pri-
vate contract principles.
116
Unlike administrative law, contract law
prohibits unilateral amendment at the behest of the agency or uni-
lateral interpretation in the form of guidance documents. Thus, an
agency may find itself, even if only temporarily, bound to a bad bar-
gain and unable to alter it through a simple interpretive decision or
rulemaking process. States may choose to avoid these complications
by codifying contractual terms in state law or promulgating them as
regulations. This would create accountability of a sort, but perhaps
113. See NEGOTIATING THE NEW HEALTH SYSTEM, supra note 112, http://www.gwumc.
edu/chrp/overview/overview.htm; see also Iglehart, supra note 112, at 995.
114. NEGOTIATING THE NEW HEALTH SYSTEM, supra note 112, http://www.gwumc.
edu/chrp/overview/overview.htm.
115. Pursuant to state plans filed with the federal government, states are obligated to
provide care to Medicaid patients in a manner consistent with statutory and regulatory
standards. See id. As the report notes, residual liability from poor contract drafting is
“unique to Medicaid.” Id. Health benefit plans offered by private employers are governed
by the Employment Retirement Income Security Act, which imposes “almost no federal
content or structural requirements[,] and [they] are exempt from most state laws.” Id.
116. See id.
184 FLORIDA STATE UNIVERSITY LAW REVIEW [Vol. 28:155
at the expense of flexibility. Codification and promulgation necessar-
ily render the contracting process more cumbersome, time consum-
ing, and rigid.
117
At this stage in their development, Medicaid contracts vary widely
across states; some are highly specific, leaving little discretion to
managed care plans, while others delegate substantial discretion to
contractors in making coverage, operational, and administrative de-
cisions.
118
Under most contracts, private companies rather than
states select and design their provider networks and oversee provider
performance.
119
The need to monitor their contracts with MCOs poses
significant challenges for state bureaucracies, which frequently lack
a comprehensive approach to data collection and processing.
120
State
monitoring of MCOs may be even more attenuated than their moni-
toring of other health care delivery institutions, such as nursing
homes, because of the intermediary role played by private quality as-
surance bodies like the NCQA. A managed care regime may rely
more heavily on independent accreditation and private assessments
of quality of care even though assessments are more difficult to make
in the managed care environment than in the hospital setting.
121
Fi-
nally, some observers argue that states will wield limited influence
with MCOs, which serve a broad array of nongovernmental clients,
such as private employers.
122
As in the nursing home environment, consumers enjoy few oppor-
tunities for redress in the Medicaid managed care regime. Patients
often lack the information and resources necessary to challenge bene-
fit denials or protest substandard care in managed care organiza-
117. The report notes that a few states have codified the service and performance
specifications in Medicaid managed care contracts in state regulations. This “merger of
regulation and contract” gives the state the flexibility to unilaterally interpret contractual
provisions and receive deference from courts. It also enables the agency to make unilateral
post-contract modifications obviating the need for negotiating amendments. Thus, con-
tracts from these states may provide only a framework for incorporating the relevant regu-
lations. See id.
118. See id.
119. See id.
120. Reporting requirements can be idiosyncratic. States have differential capacities
both to identify the information that would be most useful and to analyze it critically. See
id. (noting the need for Medicaid agencies to supplement internal analytic capabilities
through agreements with other state agencies and institutions specializing in data analy-
sis).
121. Given the relatively short periods of time for which most Medicaid beneficiaries
are eligible for the program (and hence managed care coverage), and the special needs of
this population, commercial standards of quality are relatively uninformative. Thus, spe-
cial methodologies beyond those used in traditional private accreditation might be neces-
sary to evaluate whether MCOs provide the Medicaid population adequate care. See id. For
the claim that private health care providers may not be as familiar with Medicaid benefici-
aries as public providers, see Jane Perkins & Kristi Olson, An Advocate’s Primer on Medi-
caid Managed Care Contracting, CLEARINGHOUSE REV., May-June 1997, at 19, 21.
122. Interview with Sharon Connors, Consultant, Medimetrix, Boston, Mass. (Aug. 17,
1999).
2000] CONTRACTING STATE 185
tions.
123
Even though the Balanced Budget Act requires MCOs to es-
tablish internal grievance procedures, many of the same obstacles to
consumer enforcement of agency-provider contracts identified in the
nursing home examplejudicial reluctance to declare MCOs state
actors, absence of private rights of action, and tenuous third-party
beneficiary claimsapply in this context.
124
Due Process claims, for
the most part, fail: only rarely will private health care providers be
declared state actors.
125
Indeed, the Supreme Court recently vacated
a Ninth Circuit decision holding HMO denials of Medicare services to
be state action subject to the Due Process Clause.
126
iii. Private Prisons.Both the federal and state governments
have begun contracting with private actors to provide more contro-
123. See Boese, supra note 103, at 59-62. Patients with grievances about managed care
plans have little recourse because the Employee Retirement Income Security Act (ERISA)
preempts most of their legal claims and limits them to an ERISA appeals process under
which they may recover only wrongfully denied benefits and attorney’s fees. See id. at 59-
60. Boese’s article examines the growth of qui tam actions brought pursuant to the Federal
False Claims Act as a mechanism for disgruntled patients to sue managed care organiza-
tions for substandard care, underutilization of health care services, and violations of fed-
eral regulations. See id. at 60-62. Courts have grown more receptive to patient attempts to
sue MCOs in negligence and wrongful death actions. See Robert Pear, Series of Rulings
Eases Constraints on Suing HMO’s, N.Y. TIMES, Aug. 15, 1999, at A1.
124. For an overview of consumers’ procedural rights under both Medicare and Medi-
caid, see Kinney, supra note 26, at 67-73.
125. Two leading reports on the BBA seem unduly optimistic about this possibility. See
1 SARA ROSENBAUM ET AL., GEORGE WASHINGTON UNIV. MED. CTR., NEGOTIATING THE
NEW HEALTH SYSTEM: A NATIONWIDE STUDY OF MEDICAID MANAGED CARE CONTRACTS (3d
ed. 1999), http://www.gwu.edu/~chsrp /MANGA (last visited Apr. 7, 2000) (text accompany-
ing notes 39-40); ANDY SCHNEIDER, THE KAISER COMMN ON THE FUTURE OF MEDICAID,
OVERVIEW OF MEDICAID MANAGED CARE PROVISIONS IN THE BALANCED BUDGET ACT OF
1997, at 27 (1997), http://www.kff.org/content/archive/2102 (last visited Apr. 7, 2000). Both
reports cite Daniels v. Wadley, 926 F. Supp. 1305 (M.D. Tenn. 1996), for the proposition
that beneficiaries enjoy constitutional due process rights against MCOs. In fact, the dis-
trict court’s state action finding in Daniels (itself based on a dubious reading of the Su-
preme Court’s state action jurisprudence) was vacated in part on appeal. See Daniels v.
Menke, 145 F.3d 1330 (6th Cir. 1998) (unpublished table decision). The Kaiser report also
refers to the possibility that Medicaid enrollees will enforce MCO-state agency contracts in
third-party beneficiary claims, but the relevant law is mixed at best. See Perkins & Olson,
supra note 121, at 33 (citing a “multitude of tests being used to determine third-party
beneficiary status”).
126. See Grijalva v. Shalala, 152 F.3d 1115, 1120 (9th Cir. 1998), vacated, 526 U.S.
1096 (1999). The Court remanded the case for consideration in light of American Manufac-
turers Mutual Insurance Co. v. Sullivan , 526 U.S. 40, 50 (1999), which held that a private
insurer’s decision, made pursuant to the state worker’s compensation statute, to suspend
payment of a health benefit pending utilization review was not state action. See Grijalva v.
Shalala, 526 U.S. 1096, 1096 (1999). However, the Court also instructed the Ninth Circuit
to consider the Balanced Budget Act of 1997 along with HHS’ implementing regulations,
which confer procedural rights upon patients. See id.; see also Balanced Budget Act of
1997, Pub. L. No. 105-33, §§ 4001-4002, 111 Stat. 251, 275-327. The Ninth Circuit in Gri-
jalva had distinguished Blum v. Yaretsky, 457 U.S. 991 (1982), and reasoned that HMOs
and the federal government were joint participants in the Medicare provision. See Gri-
jalva, 152 F.3d at 1120.
186 FLORIDA STATE UNIVERSITY LAW REVIEW [Vol. 28:155
versial functions, such as incarceration.
127
The Federal Bureau of
Prisons and a variety of state corrections departments currently rely
on private for-profit companies to house a small percentage of the na-
tion’s inmates.
128
Today, at least thirty-four states plus Puerto Rico
have passed enabling statutes legalizing the delegation of prison op-
erations to private firms.
129
Like advocates of privatization in other
contexts, proponents of private prison management claim that priva-
tization will increase both efficiency and quality: Motivated by profit
and unburdened by civil service employment constraints, private
companies promise to build prisons more quickly and at lower cost
than can public agencies.
130
In an era of significant prison expansion
and skyrocketing prices, privatization offers the taxpayer very at-
tractive cost savings.
Even in publicly operated prisons, private firms provide basic
goods such as food, bedding, and clothing, along with medical, reha-
bilitative, vocational, and transportation services. In addition, both
federal and state governments contract with the private sector to
build and maintain prison infrastructure, and to supply everything
from bulletproof vests to security systems. And private involvement
127. See Laura Suzanne Farris, Comment, Private Jails in Oklahoma: An Unconstitu-
tional Delegation of Legislative Authority, 33 TULSA L.J. 959, 959 (1998) (noting the trend
toward “privatization” and stating that 120 private jails and prisons are operating in 27
states).
128. Private prisons house less than 10% of the 1.8 million Americans currently behind
bars. See Nzong Xiong, Private Prisons: A Question of Savings, N.Y. TIMES, July 13, 1997,
at C5 (reporting that private prisons in the United States held more than 85,000 inmates
in 1996).
129. I thank Sharon Dolovich for sharing her research on the enabling statutes. See
ALASKA STAT. § 33.30.031(a) (Lexis 1998); ARIZ. REV. STAT. ANN. § 41-1609(B) (West 1999);
ARK. CODE ANN. § 12-50-106(a) (Michie 1999); CAL. PENAL CODE § 6256 (2000); COLO. REV.
STAT. ANN. § 17-26.5-101 (2000); CONN. GEN. STAT. ANN. § 18-86b(a) (West 1998); D.C.
CODE ANN. § 24-1201(c) (Supp. 2000); FLA. STAT. § 944.105(1) (2000); IDAHO CODE § 20-
209(2) (1997); KY. REV. STAT. ANN. § 197.505(1) (Michie 1998); LA. REV. STAT. ANN. §
39:1800.4(A) (Supp. 2000); MISS. CODE ANN. § 47-4-1(1) (1993); MONT. CODE ANN. § 53-30-
106(3) (1999); NEB. REV. STAT. § 83-176(2) (1999); NEV. REV. STAT. § 209.141 (1999); N.H.
REV. STAT. ANN. § 21-H:8 (VI) (2000); N.M. STAT. ANN. § 33-1-17(A) (Michie 1998); N.C.
GEN. STAT. § 148-37(b1) (1999); N.D. CENT. CODE § 12-44.1-02 (1997); OHIO REV. CODE
ANN. § 9.06(A)(1) (Anderson Supp. 1999); OKLA. STAT. ANN. tit. 11 § 34-105(A) (West
1999); OR. REV. STAT. § 423.100 (1999) (containing in notes the “Temporary Provisions Re-
lating to Authority of Department to Contract for Out-Of-State Correctional Facilities and
Services”); P.R. LAWS ANN. tit. 4 § 1112(o) (Supp. 1998); S.D. CODIFIED LAWS § 24-11-42
(Michie 2000); TENN. CODE ANN. § 41-24-103(a) (1999); TEX. GOV T CODE ANN. § 495.001(a)
(West 2000); UTAH CODE ANN. § 10-8-58.5(1)(a) (1999); VA. CODE ANN. § 53.1-266 (Michie
2000); W.VA. CODE § 25-5-2 (2000); WIS. STAT. ANN. § 301.08(1)(b)(1) (West 1999); WYO.
STAT. ANN. § 7-22-102(a) (Michie 1999). But see 730 ILL. COMP. STAT. ANN. 140/3 (West
1997) (forbidding private prisons in the state); KAN. STAT. ANN. § 75-52,133 (1997) (same);
MO. ANN. STAT. § 70.220 (West 1998) (same); 61 PA. CONS. STAT. ANN. §1083(a) (2000)
(“Private Prison Moratorium and Study Act”).
130. Up to two thirds of a prison’s operating costs are personnel-related. See Kevin
Acker, Off with Their Overhead: More Prison Bars for the Buck, POLY REV., Fall 1999, at
73, 73.
2000] CONTRACTING STATE 187
in public correctional facilities goes beyond contracts for goods and
services. So in one sense, a robust private role in public persons is
not new.
Sociologists already describe corrections as a “subgovernment,” a
network of organizations comprised of federal agencies, for-profit
corporations, and professional associations.
131
Nongovernmental pro-
fessional groups such the American Correctional Association (ACA),
an organization of correctional professionals that dates from 1870,
exert considerable influence over correctional policy. The ACA per-
forms a variety of functions that shape corrections policy, including
training personnel and accrediting agencies and programs.
132
Indeed,
ACA standards govern most aspects of prison operation.
133
Contract-
ing out the management of prisons to for-profit companies represents
a step on the continuum of “private dependence” (that is, govern-
ment’s dependence on private entities to perform its functions), then,
rather than a dramatic shift toward private actors.
Still, this step is a rather significant one. Prison privatization has
spurred a vigorous debate in the legal, political, and policy communi-
ties and produced an enormous volume of literature.
134
Of all the ser-
vices and functions currently contracted out, incarceration appears to
attract the most visceral opposition. Those who object to prison pri-
vatization reject it on moral as well as pragmatic grounds. For exam-
ple, John DiIulio has argued that incarceration is so inherently pub-
lic that it is immoral to privatize it.
135
Although private incarceration may be more troubling than con-
tracting with private parties to deliver social services, many of the
131. J. Robert Lilly & Paul Knepper, The Corrections-Commercial Comp lex, 39 CRIME
& DELINQ. 150, 151 (1993). The authors argue that participants in subgovernments share
a close working relationship marked by cooperation and compromise and that subgovern-
ments feature overlap between societal interest and the government bureaucracy in ques-
tion. “The line between the public good and private interest becomes blurred as govern-
mental and nongovernmental institutions become harder to distinguish.” Id. at 153.
132. See id. at 156-57.
133. Throughout its history, the ACA has foste red professionalism in prison admini-
stration through the development of standards and promoted progressive reforms such as
rehabilitation. See MALCOLM M. FEELEY & EDWARD L. RUBIN, JUDICIAL POLICY MAKING
AND THE MODERN STATE : HOW THE COURTS REFORMED AMERICAS PRISONS 162-63 (1998).
The ACA provides standards for security and control, food service, sanitation and hygiene,
medical and health care, inmate rights, work programs, educational programs, recrea-
tional activities, library services, records, and personnel issues. See Hart et al., supra note
80, at 1149 (1997).
134. See, e.g., PRIVATE PRISONS AND THE PUBLIC INTEREST, supra note 73; DAVID
SCHICOR, PUNISHMENT FOR PROFIT: PRIVATE PRISONS /PUBLIC CONCERNS (1995); DiIulio,
Jr., supra note 77, at 66; Robbins, supra note 81; Joseph E. Field, Note, Making Prisons
Private: An Improper Delegation of a Governmental Power, 15 HOFSTRA L. REV. 649 (1987).
135. See DiIulio, Jr., supra note 74, at 155, 173, 176. For an argument that the market
is not an appropriate mechanism for producing and distributing collective goods such as
education and health care, see WALZER, supra note 73, at 86, 198. For an argument that
prison privatization may not produce the anticipated efficiencies, see DONAHUE, supra note
2, at 160-65.
188 FLORIDA STATE UNIVERSITY LAW REVIEW [Vol. 28:155
obstacles to effective oversight appear to be similar. The ultimate
beneficiaries of the incarceration functionwhether one considers
them to be taxpayers, prisoners, or bothface considerable obstacles
to meaningful oversight. The typical taxpayer encounters few oppor-
tunities or incentives to monitor conditions in prisons. Although pris-
oners may file suits alleging violations of their constitutional rights,
and while families and prisoners’ rights advocates may help to moni-
tor conditions in prisons, the relative invisibility and low moral
status of the prison population makes prisoners especially vulnerable
and heightens the need for accountability.
136
As with nursing homes providing health care, the private provider
in this example is one step further removed than a public agency
from direct accountability to the electorate.
137
Moreover, the incar-
ceration function, like quality health care, may be difficult to specify
in contractual terms.
138
Finally, the incarceration example raises
most strikingly the problem of potential conflicts of interest between
public and private goals. That is, the private interest in maximizing
profits may conflict with the public interest in sound correctional
policies. Private prison officials and private guards exercise discre-
tion over every aspect of the prisoners’ daily experience: meals,
health care, recreation, cell conditions, transportation, work assign-
ments, visitation, and parole. Private prison officials determine when
infractions occur, impose punishments and, perhaps most signifi-
cantly, make recommendations to parole boards.
139
Their discretion
affects prisoners’ most fundamental liberty and security interests.
Under pressure to generate profits, private prison operators could
choose to lower costs by minimizing staff or hiring underqualified
guards, or by providing minimally adequate but nonetheless sub-
standard medical care.
136. For a description and historical analysis of the procedural mechanisms available
to prisoners, including writs of habeas corpus, constitutional claims, and suits pursuant to
the Civil Rights Act, see FEELEY & RUBIN, supra note 133, at 31.
137. This raises a concern about democratic accountability analogous to that voiced by
Justice O’Connor in New York v. United States, 505 U.S. 144, 168-69 (1992), that citizens
might be confused when they cannot identify the level of government responsible for a
given policy.
138. See Michael O’Hare et al., The Privatization of Imprisonment: A Managerial Per-
spective, in PRIVATE PRISONS AND THE PUBLIC INTEREST, supra note 73, at 112 (“Indeed, in-
formation flow, product specification, and control are the critical factors in the managerial
analyis of privatization . . . .”).
139. See Field, supra note 134, at 661.
2000] CONTRACTING STATE 189
IV. REGULATORY CONTRACTS
A. Regulation as Negotiation
The contracts discussed thus far might be described as contracts
for implementation of public policy, rather than its formulation. In
addition, they might be characterized as contracts to deliver benefits
and provide services, rather than contracts designed to implement
coercive regulations. Notwithstanding that these contracts contain
important regulatory features, their principal purpose is to procure a
service such as waste collection or provide a valuable benefit such as
government-financed health care.
Regulatory contracts are another matter. To the extent that con-
tracts have arisen in the regulatory process, they serve as an alter-
native to traditional agency-directed implementation. To be sure,
these contractual or quasi-contractual regulatory instruments differ
significantly from the other public-private contracts discussed so far.
Regulatory contracts might arise for different reasons than contracts
to deliver social services or perform arguably public functions. Per-
haps agencies turn to contractual regulatory instruments not for the
reasons that explain contracting out generally, but simply because
contracts with regulated entities appease a congress hostile to regu-
lation, or because they pacify powerful industry groups committed to
resisting regulation through legal challenge. Moreover, the piecemeal
use of regulatory contract can seem less threatening to the ultimate
power of the state than widespread contracting out, which some ob-
servers believe is more likely to shrink or weaken public institutions
in relation to the market.
Finally, one might argue, from a traditional administrative law
perspective most contractual regulatory instruments really amount
to instances of agency discretion, and as such, can be relatively easily
constrained. By contrast, contracting out is more difficult to control;
outsourcing functions to private actors removes them from the reach
of most discretion-constraining oversight tools altogether. In sum,
from a traditional perspective, that regulatory contracts happen to
take the form of contract makes little difference. With these instru-
ments, the only relevant question for the administrative law scholar
is whether, in resorting to contract as opposed to another mode of
implementation, the agency has operated within the bounds of its
lawfully delegated discretion.
And yet, emphasizing the contractual nature of these toolsand
pairing them with the phenomenon of contracting outhighlights
the special problems that contractual instruments of all sorts pose
for accountability. This enables us to dig beneath the veneer of for-
mal accountability, which a traditional focus on discretion fails to
190 FLORIDA STATE UNIVERSITY LAW REVIEW [Vol. 28:155
penetrate. That is, where the discretion-oriented analysis demands
only formal authorization for the agency’s use of contractual instru-
ments, or broad enough discretion to accommodate the agency’s
choice of contract, a focus on the contractual mode itself asks
whether, even where lawful, the use of contract might undermine
important norms and interests. Treating contractual regulatory in-
struments as something more than every other instance of discretion
enables us to determine whether there is something especially trou-
bling about contract as a mechanism of governance, even when the
individual examples of contract differ from one another along a num-
ber of dimensions.
To date, there is no formal contractual mechanism for either es-
tablishing or implementing regulatory standards. Indeed, the notion
of private contract is anathema to public regulation. And yet, to a
significant extent, negotiation and exchange pervade the regulatory
process. This observation is at once banal and too frequently over-
looked.
140
It is banal in the sense that it was precisely the pervasive-
ness of secret, informal bargains that vindicated capture theory and
prompted the procedural administrative law reforms of the 1960s.
These judicially imposed reforms opened the administrative process
to public scrutiny and both balanced and structured private influ-
ence, developments that Richard Stewart captured so effectively in
his interest representation model of administrative law.
141
At the same time, the full impact of negotiation and exchange has
been overlooked to the extent that it pervades implementation and
enforcement as well as rulemaking. Even in a command-and-control
system, the regulatory process is deeply, if informally, contractual.
For example, regulated entities negotiate the terms of their permits
and litigants frequently settle conflicts through negotiated consent
decrees. That is, the procedural reforms Professor Stewart identified
were designed to structure only part of the “regime of exchange” that
constitutes the regulatory process.
142
In fact, the conceptual distinction between contract and regulation
may not be as clear as we think.
143
Regulation does not conform to an
140. See generally CORNELIUS M. KERWIN, RULEMAKING: HOW GOVERNMENT AGENCIES
WRITE LAW AND MAKE POLICY (1994) (“Negotiated rulemaking is now a mature concept
with a considerable, and largely positive, track record in the development of rules.”).
141. See Stewart, supra note 12, at 1760-89.
142. See id. at 1670.
143. See Geoffrey C. Hazard, Jr. & Eric W. Orts, Environmental Contracts in the
United States, in ENVIRONMENTAL CONTRACTS AND REGULATORY INNOVATION:
COMPARATIVE APPROACHES IN EUROPE AND THE UNITED STATES (K. Deketelaere & E. Orts
eds., forthcoming 2000) (manuscript at 9-10, on file with author) (contrasting contract and
regulation, but claiming that the differences are of degree rather than kind). To give just a
sample of the Hazard and Orts list of comparative attributes, contracts require party as-
sent while regulation requires party submission, and contracts involve participation in the
process while regulation demands subjugation to the process. See id.
2000] CONTRACTING STATE 191
idealized hierarchical model of government power, in which agencies
directly deliver services or unilaterally impose rules on regulated en-
tities under threat of sanction. Instead, the regulatory process can be
understood as a set of residual choices that must be made by regu-
lated entities, together with government and other interested par-
ties, after some of the choices have been ruled out. This understand-
ing focuses attention on the space left for working out the content of
the regulation and its implementation, rather than on the initial
move by the state to shrink that space. At virtually every step in the
regulatory processstandard setting, implementation, and enforce-
mentthe state forecloses some options and conditions others.
Within the constrained space of permissible choices, then, nego-
tiation is common and constant. Gerd Winter describes the imple-
mentation process as a “bartering” system in which an agency’s dis-
cretion gives it room to maneuver;
144
John Scholz characterizes en-
forcement in similar terms.
145
In this space, the relevant actors (gov-
ernmental and nongovernmental parties) make and execute agree-
ments and rely on each other’s promises.
146
Repeat players establish
cultures, understandings, and norms that govern their behavior.
147
Their arrangements may be structured by legal entitlements, but
these play a background or shadow role.
This informal system of obligation and exchange may be a staple
of agency decisionmaking, but from the perspective of administrative
law, it must be tracked and constrained. To prevent agencies from
abusing their discretion and to avoid agency capture by regulated in-
terests, administrative law seeks to cabin the informal space for bar-
ter, primarily, though not exclusively, through judicial review. It is in
this contextone largely hostile to the notion of regulatory bar-
gainsthat experiments with regulatory contracts have nonetheless
begun to emerge.
B. Experiments in “Contractual” Regulation
While in their infancy, these experiments have developed suffi-
ciently to merit the attention of legal scholars. Contractual regula-
tory instruments consist of a handful of loosely defined innovations,
distinguishable from conventional approaches because they feature
negotiation, bargain, and/or consensus among stakeholders, and be-
cause they usually manifest themselves in written agreements. This
includes not only regulatory negotiation, but also examples like
144. Gerd Winter, Bartering Rationality in Regulation, 19 L. & SOCY REV. 219, 221,
225 (1985).
145. See John T. Scholz, Cooperation, Deterrence and the Ecology of Regulatory En-
forcement, 18 L. & SOCY REV. 179, 180-81 (1984).
146. See Winter, supra note 144, at 221-22.
147. See id. at 230-32.
192 FLORIDA STATE UNIVERSITY LAW REVIEW [Vol. 28:155
EPA’s Project XL and a host of other implementation and enforce-
ment strategies that run the gamut from standard setting to imple-
mentation and enforcement, most of which have developed in envi-
ronmental or health and safety regulation. For example, Caldart and
Ashford recently identified a number of OSHA and EPA efforts to in-
formally negotiate implementation and compliance with regulated
entities.
148
Congress has explicitly authorized some of these initia-
tives, while others are instances of agency enforcement discretion, as
when an agency agrees not to enforce formal legal requirements in
exchange for a regulated entity’s agreement to perform obligations
not required by formal law. Although these agreements are not en-
forceable, David Dana argues that they exemplify a “contractarian”
approach to regulation.
149
Regulatory negotiationa formal consensus-based stakeholder
process for developing regulationsis probably the most frequently
cited example of a contract-like instrument.
150
In passing the Negoti-
ated Rulemaking Act (NRA), Congress authorized agencies to use
this nontraditional method of rule development (reg-neg) when agen-
cies believe it to be in “the public interest” after considering a num-
ber of factors, including whether the agency can convene a balanced
negotiating committee capable of representing the interests that will
be significantly affected by the rule.
151
Reg-neg was originally in-
tended to achieve a number of goals, including improved rule quality
148. See Charles C. Caldart & Nicholas A. Ashford, Negotiation as a Means of Develop-
ing and Implementing Environmental and Occupational Health and Safety Policy, 23
HARV. ENVTL. L. REV. 141, 180-93 (1999).
149. David Dana, The Emerging Regulatory Contract Paradigm in Environmental
Regulation, 2000 U. ILL. L. REV. 35, 35, 38-44. Dana considers HCPs, Project XL, Brown-
fields, and SEPs.
150. See Negotiated Rulemaking Act (NRA), 5 U.S.C. §§ 561-570 (1994 & Supp. V
1999). Congress passed the NRA to endorse and formalize a negotiation process that agen-
cies were already experimenting with and that had been endorsed by the Administrative
Conference. See Procedures for Negotiating Proposed Regulations (Recommendation 82-4),
1 C.F.R. § 305.82-4 (1993), available in LEXIS, Exec. Library, CFR93 File, removed by 58
Fed. Reg. 54,271 (Oct. 21, 1993). For a history of negotiated rulemaking, see Philip J. Har-
ter, Negotiating Regulations: A Cure for Malaise, 71 GEO. L.J. 1, 2-18 (1982). Although the
statute authorizes reg-negs, it also requires that the consensus rules go through notice and
comment. See id. at 101.
151. See 5 U.S.C. § 563. Since it was first proposed in the early 1980s, regulatory nego-
tiation has generated a veritable cottage industry of administrative law scholarship, with
commentators believing it to be, variously, an interesting minor reform, a model for the fu-
ture, or an unmitigated evil. Most administrative law scholars probably fall into the first
camp. See, e.g., Susan Rose -Ackerman, Consensus Versus Incentives: A Skeptical Look at
Regulatory Negotiation, 43 DUKE L.J. 1206 (1994). I am usually placed in the second camp.
See Jody Freeman, Collaborative Governance in the Administrative State, 45 UCLA L. REV.
1 (1997). For a member of the last camp, see William Funk, Bargaining Toward the New
Millennium: Regulatory Negotiation and the Subversion of the Public Interest, 46 DUKE
L.J. 1351 (1997). For an argument that regulatory negotiation has failed to deliver on its
promised benefits, see Cary Coglianese, Assessing Consensus: The Promise and Perform-
ance of Negotiated Rulemaking, 46 DUKE L.J. 1255, 1258-61 (1997).
2000] CONTRACTING STATE 193
and greater legitimacy for the resulting rules. Early proponents also
expected that it would reduce litigation and conserve resources by
bringing parties likely to challenge the rule or obstruct its implemen-
tation directly into the development process.
152
Its innovation was to
bring principles of alternative dispute resolution to rulemakingin
the form of direct negotiations among the affected partiesin order
to ameliorate the adversarialism that had come to characterize the
conventional approach.
153
Because negotiated rules must still go through the notice-and-
comment process and because the convening agency is not bound to
promulgate the consensus rule, reg-neg falls well short of embodying
a formal contract.
154
Still, reg-neg is a meaningful example of a con-
tract-like mechanism. Participants in a reg-neg clearly form alli-
ances, stake out positions, and bargain. Typically, they sign an
agreement not to legally challenge any rule produced by a consensus
of which they are a part.
155
Although these agreements are unlikely
to be legally enforceable, there may be a price for noncompliance,
particularly for repeat players who face informal sanctions and repu-
tational costs.
156
At a minimum, the parties in a reg-neg clearly take
their participation seriously (devoting significant time and resources
to it) and they expect their consensus to form the basis of the final
rule.
Beyond the rule-writing process, the implementation stage of
regulation has produced a number of contract-like innovations. For
example, the EPA has adopted a quasi-contractual approach to im-
plementing environmental regulations in its Project XL initiative,
152. See Jody Freeman & Laura I. Langbein, Regulatory Negotiation and the Legiti-
macy Benefit, 9 N.Y.U. ENVTL. L.J. 60, 68-69 (2000) (explaining the claims made by early
proponents of reg-neg).
153. Although some scholars view reg-neg simply as a bargaining exercise, in my view
the parties on a reg-neg committee do more than trade interests. Direct participation in
rule development can enable creative problem solving, increase learning, improve relation-
ships and, at least according to participants, facilitate rule implementation. See Freeman,
supra note 151, at 26-28, 36 (explaining reg-neg as problem solving). See also Freeman &
Langbein, supra note 152, at 62 (pointing to empirical evidence that participants in reg-
neg report significantly more learning than participants in conventional rulemaking, view
negotiated rules as likely to be successfully implemented, and report higher satisfaction
partly because they obtain a higher quality rule).
154. See 5 U.S.C. § 553 (requiring notice and comment); see also USA Group Loan
Servs. v. Riley, 82 F.3d 708, 714-15 (7th Cir. 1996) (holding that the promise to bargain in
good faith is not enforceable under the NRA and that the agency may depart from the con-
sensus when promulgating a rule).
155. See Freeman & Langbein, supra note 152, at 92 n.154 (citing an example of such
an agreement).
156. See id. at 213 (explaining the implications of signing agreements not to sue, even
if they are unenforceable). Reg-negs promulgated intact after negotiations are “remarkably
resistant to substantive changes.” Philip J. Harter, Assessing the Assessors: The Actual
Performance of Negotiated Rulemaking, 9 N.Y.U. ENVTL. L.J. 32, 51 (2000). Harter ana-
lyzes the data provided in Coglianese’s study, supra note 151. See Harter, supra, at 49-52.
194 FLORIDA STATE UNIVERSITY LAW REVIEW [Vol. 28:155
the national pilot program designed to test methods of achieving su-
perior and more cost-effective environmental protection through pro-
ject agreements with individual facilities or industry sectors.
157
Through XL, the agency exercises its enforcement discretion to go
one step beyond the informal negotiation that already occurs in the
traditional permitting process, by granting regulatory flexibility to
applicants in exchange for commitments to achieve better environ-
mental performance than might otherwise be achieved through com-
pliance with applicable regulations.
158
The idea is to allow firms to
devise innovative compliance strategies that result in a net environ-
mental benefit in exchange for relief from rigid regulations.
In a typical XL project, the EPA might grant a single, streamlined
permit that authorizes cross-pollutant and cross-media trades that
might not otherwise be allowed by regulations.
159
XL allows the
agency to grant preapproval of process changes or emissions in-
creases that would normally trigger a lengthy separate approval
process.
160
While these initiatives do not produce legally enforceable
contracts, they culminate in detailed, written documents known as
final project agreements (FPAs). XL thus has some contractual fea-
tures: the parties bargain, they produce written agreements, and
they undertake mutual commitments. The terms and conditions of
the FPAs are then incorporated into permits, which are legally en-
forceable.
161
Habitat conservation planning is perhaps the most visible exam-
ple of a consensus-based, multi-stakeholder approach to resource
management, and one explicitly authorized by Congress in the En-
dangered Species Act (ESA).
162
Under section 10(a) of the ESA, the
Secretary of Interior may issue a permit to allow an otherwise im-
permissible “incidental take” of a threatened or endangered species,
provided the applicant submits a satisfactory “conservation plan”
(HCP).
163
Among other things, the plan must ensure that the “take”
will not “appreciably reduce the likelihood of the survival and recov-
157. See Lawrence E. Susskind & Joshua Secunda, The Risks and the Advantages of
Agency Discretion: Evidence from EPA’s Project XL, 17 UCLA J. ENVTL. L. & POLY 67, 84-
85 (1998/99). In addition to firms and industry sectors, federal facilities and communities
might sponsor XL projects. The EPA selects projects that will produce superior environ-
mental performance, provide regulatory flexibility, and ensure stakeholder involvement.
See id. at 85.
158. See Regulatory Reinvention (XL) Pilot Projects, 60 Fed. Reg. 27,282 (solicitation of
proposals and request for comment, May 23, 1995).
159. Cross-pollutant trades allow permit holders to produce more of one pollutant but
less of another. Cross-media trades allow holders to degrade more of one medium but less
of another.
160. See Susskind & Secunda, supra note 157, at 86.
161. See id.
162. See Endangered Species Act §§ 9-18, 16 U.S.C. §§ 1531-44 (1994 & West Supp.
2000).
163. Id. § 10(a), 16 U.S.C. § 1539(a) (1994).
2000] CONTRACTING STATE 195
ery of the species in the wild.”
164
Thus, HCPs amount to mitigation
measures designed to minimize the impact of a proposed action (usu-
ally a development project) on a threatened or endangered species.
165
Although the only truly indispensable parties in the HCP negotia-
tion process are those whose actions may result in the taking, many
HCP negotiations include a diversity of stakeholders, including
community groups, environmental organizations, scientists and other
experts, and nonprofit land conservation groups. As with regulatory
negotiation, the federal agency (here the Fish and Wildlife Service)
participates in the negotiations but is also statutorily obligated to in-
dependently determine the adequacy of the plan, submit the plan to
public comment, and then decide whether to issue the permit.
166
J.B. Ruhl describes HCP agreements as “quasi-contractual” even
though they are incorporated into permits.
167
The permitting process
itself is “a structured negotiation” in which the applicant negotiates
with the agency to design a “development scenario that is compatible
with the conservation goals of the ESA as well as the economic goals
of development in general.”
168
Reinforcing the “contractual” image of
the HCP process, the Fish and Wildlife Service recently adopted a
“no surprise” policy by regulation. The policy assures HCP permit-
tees that the agency will impose no additional burdens on them in
the event of changed circumstances.
169
A contractual approach is currently built into the agency enforce-
ment process as well, in the form of “supplemental enforcement
plans” (SEPs) by which agencies waive monetary penalties in ex-
change for remedial measures to which the regulated entity may not
other wise submit. Proponents of this enforcement innovation argue
that SEPs are more problem oriented than conventional penalty as-
sessment; they claim that SEPs provide both short- and long-term
164. Id. § 10(a), 16 U.S.C. § 1539(a)(2)(B)(iv). The requirements of section 10(a) largely
mirror the contents of the San Bruno HCP, which had been developed independently in re-
sponse to a conflict between proposed development and the habitat of a threatened butte r-
fly species. The plan was developed by the parties without specific ESA authorization. The
parties subsequently urged Congress to amend the ESA to allow a permitting exemption
based on the plan. The San Bruno HCP was formally accepted by the Department of the
Interior and a permit was issued following passage of the 1982 amendments. See Endan-
gered Species Act Amendments of 1982, Pub. L. No. 97-304, 96 Stat. 1411; Robert D.
Thornton, Searching for Consensus and Predictability: Habitat Conservation Planning Un-
der the Endangered Species Act of 1973, 21 ENVTL. L. 605, 624-26 (1991).
165. See Thornton, supra note 164, at 625.
166. See MICHAEL J. BEAN ET AL., RECONCILING CONFLICTS UNDER THE ENDANGERED
SPECIES ACT: THE HABITAT CONSERVATION PLANNING EXPERIENCE 12-13 (1991).
167. J.B. Ruhl, How to Kill Endangered Species, Legally: The Nuts and Bolts of En-
dangered Species Act “HCP” Permits for Real Estate Development, 5 ENVTL. LAW. 346, 400
(1999).
168. Id.
169. See Habitat Conservation Plan Assurances (“No Surprises”) Rule, 63 Fed. Reg.
8859, 8871-73 (1998) (codified at 50 C.F.R. pt. 222).
196 FLORIDA STATE UNIVERSITY LAW REVIEW [Vol. 28:155
benefits by enabling firms to identify opportunities for technological
change that might have additional beneficial environmental effects
beyond the immediate lawsuit.
170
For the most part, however, environmental contracting is in an
early developmental phase. To take effect, most such agreements still
require independent agency action such as rule promulgation or
permit issuance, and most purport to be independently unenforce-
able.
171
Still, both Congress and individual agencies appear willing to
experiment with regulatory contracts, and a handful of scholars find
them promising enough to pursue as an alternative approach.
172
For
example, Don Elliott has proposed that “command and covenant”
might replace command-and-control regulation.
173
Based on an XL-
like approach, this model would rely on a government-established
minimum standard of performance, while allowing regulated entities
to essentially contract around regulatory inefficiencies by devising
implementation strategies. Dan Farber recently described efforts
such as reg-neg and Project XL as illustrations of a bilateral bargain-
ing model of regulation, and he suggested that it seems the “most
promising” way to conceptualize regulation.
174
170. See Caldart & Ashford, supra note 148, at 191 (citing an EPA report claiming that
company representatives credited the SEP process with this benefit). After analyzing the
kinds of technological changes prompted by the settlements, Caldart and Ashford claim
that there remain unexploited opportunities for using the enforcement process to stimulate
technological change. See id.
171. For example, Project XL Final Project Agreements state that they are unenforce-
able. Parties can withdraw from them at any time and revert to the default system of regu-
lation. See Susskind & Secunda, supra note 157, at 85-86.
172. See Hazard & Orts, supra note 143 (manuscript at 30). In an effort to illuminate
the already frequent use of legally enforceable contract in regulation, Orts and Hazard cite
the pervasiveness of settlement agreements that may amount to a kind of contractual
regulation by litigation. For example, settlement agreements of environmental disputes
may end up governing complex regulatory matters involving multiple parties, such as the
manner and extent of remediation of hazardous waste sites that qualify for cleanup under
the Superfund statute. See id. (manuscript at 1-2).
173. E. Donald Elliott, Toward Ecological Law and Policy, in THINKING
ECOLOGICALLY: THE NEXT GENERATION OF ENVIRONMENTAL POLICY 171, 183 (Marian
Chertow and Daniel Esty eds., 1997).
174. Daniel A. Farber, Triangulating the Future of Reinvention: Three Emerging Mo d-
els of Environmental Protection, 2000 U. ILL. L. REV. 61, 61, 76-77. Farber proposes a “bi-
lateral bargaining” model and compares it to alternatives, including a “governance” model,
which is multilateral and ecosystem-based. Id. at 62; see also Caldart & Ashford, supra
note 148, at 199-202. See generally Freeman, supra note 151, at 4-6 (proposing a collabora-
tive model of regulation in which negotiation and problem solving play a prominent role).
Farber was careful, however, to cite the problems associated with the bargaining model.
See Farber, supra, at 117-18; See also Mark Seidenfeld, Empowering Stakeholders: Limits
on Collaboration as the Basis for Flexible Regulation, 41 WM. & MARY L. REV. 411, 412-13
(2000).
Another process that fits within a broadly defined contractual approach is the Common
Sense Initiative (CSI). See U.S. GENERAL ACCOUNTING OFFICE, REGULATORY
REINVENTION: EPA’S COMMON SENSE INITIATIVE NEEDS AN IMPROVED OPERATING
FRAMEWORK AND PROGRESS MEASURES 1 (1997). CSI is an effort to devise superior regula-
tory strategies in six important industrial sectors by bringing the relevant stakeholders to-
2000] CONTRACTING STATE 197
Moreover, although a contractual regulatory model is new to the
United States, enforceable contracts are an increasingly common fea-
ture of environmental regulation in the European Union.
175
In Bel-
gium, the Netherlands, France, and Germany, a variety of contrac-
tual instruments have emerged, including “agreements” or “cove-
nants” between governments and industrial polluters, as well as
agreements between polluters and local communities.
176
Some of
these instruments are considered “voluntary” and unenforceable but
nonetheless replace procedural requirements and regulatory com-
mitments; others have the status of legally enforceable contracts.
177
Citing the European experienceand mindful of potential conflicts
between the government’s role as sovereign and its role as contract-
ing partyGeoff Hazard and Eric Orts recently suggested that we
explore the potential of contract in American regulation.
178
One need not look to Europe, however, for examples of hybrid in-
struments that combine regulation and contract. Local land use regu-
lation presents a precedent for the theory and practice of regulatory
contracting. Through contract zoning and development agreements,
local government bodies routinely bargain with private developers
and residents and reach legally enforceable agreements that contain,
among other things, regulatory freezes and exactions. This form of
government action is neither regulatory in a traditional sense nor
conventionally contractual: it depends on a convergence of regulatory
and contract power.
179
gether to negotiate the necessary changes. See Caldart & Ashford, supra note 148, at 193.
The EPA has convened advisory committees with representatives from industry, labor, e n-
vironmental, and community groups for each of the six sectors: automobile manufacturing,
computers and electronics, iron and steel, metal finishing, petroleum refining, and print-
ing. See id. EPA officials participate extensively in the process. See id. Each committee is
chaired by an EPA official and the agency provides staff support. See id.
175. See generally Eric W. Orts & Kurt Deketelaere, Introduction: Environmental Con-
tracts and Regulatory Innovation, in ENVIRONMENTAL CONTRACTS AND REGULATORY
FUNCTIONS, supra note 143 (manuscript at 5).
176. See id.
177. See id. at 7 (comparing German “self-commitments” to Dutch civil contracts).
178. See Hazard & Orts, supra note 143 (manuscript at 4-5).
179. See Carol M. Rose, Planning and Dealing: Piecemeal Land Controls as a Problem
of Local Legitimacy, 71 CAL. L. REV. 837, 892 (1983). Rose suggests that courts approach
land use deals not by classifying the government mode in terms of traditional categories of
governmental action, but by using this mediation theory. She argues that they ought to as-
sess the legitimacy of land use deals by analyzing “whether the local body went through
the steps of identifying disputants, exploring issues, and explaining results.” Id. at 900.
198 FLORIDA STATE UNIVERSITY LAW REVIEW [Vol. 28:155
C. Objections to Regulatory Contracts
1. The “Undemocratic” Critique
Traditionally, we view regulation as a top-down and prescriptive
exercise consisting of government-imposed requirements or outright
prohibitions that regulated entities must observe upon pain of civil
and criminal penalty. Establishing and enforcing regulatory stan-
dards is legally and culturally understood to be the state’s responsi-
bility.
180
In a democratic system, we expect our elected representa-
tives to be accountable for state-sponsored coercion. Although Con-
gress might delegate the bulk of the regulatory task to administra-
tive agencies, agency discretion is constrained by numerous formal
and informal accountability mechanisms, including legislative and
executive oversight, judicial review, procedural rules, and media
scrutiny. To the extent that agencies further delegate coercive regu-
latory tasks to private actors, we expect the delegates to be ade-
quately constrained by, for example, mandatory procedures and rig-
orous agency oversight. If private actors are permitted to share stan-
dard-setting authority or assume the enforcement responsibility that
lies first and foremost with the agency, we expect there to be signifi-
cant limits on their authority.
181
Although most administrative law scholars would surely acknowl-
edge that informal negotiation, bargaining, and exchange pervade
the regulatory process, none of the several competing theories of ad-
ministrative law advances the normative claim that regulation ought
180. The notion that lawmaking is the obligation of the state is rooted in Article I of
the Constitution and expressed in the nondelegation doctrine. Although individual mem-
bers of the Supreme Court occasionally threaten to invoke the nondelegation doctrine, the
doctrine has not been applied meaningfully since 1935. Nonetheless, it remains a back-
ground threat that may serve to discipline agency officials’ interpretation of their statutes.
However, the D.C. Circuit recently invoked the nondelegation doctrine, and in an uncon-
ventional way, in striking down EPA’s revised ambient air quality standards for ozone and
particulate matter established pursuant to the Clean Air Act. See American Trucking
Ass’ns v. EPA, 175 F.3d 1027 (D.C. Cir. 1999), modified on reh’g, 195 F.3d 4 (D.C. Cir.
1999). [Editor’s Note: On February 27, 2001, the Supreme Court reversed American Truck-
ing as to the nondelegation issue. Whitman v. American Trucking Ass’ns, 121 S. Ct. 903,
911-14 (2001).] For references to the nondelegation doctrine in recent Supreme Court opin-
ions, see Clinton v. City of New York, 524 U.S. 417 (1998) (invalidating line item veto); and
Industrial Union Dep’t v. American Petroleum Inst., 448 U.S. 607, 685-88 (1980)
(Rehnquist, J., concurring, on nondelegation grounds).
181. See Harold I. Abramson, A Fifth Branch of Government: The Private Regulators
and Their Constitutionality, 16 HASTINGS CONST. L.Q. 165, 181-86 (1989); Barry Boyer &
Errol Meidinger, Privatizing Regulatory Enforcement: A Preliminary Assessment of Citizen
Suits Under Federal Environmental Laws, 34 BUFF. L. REV. 833, 838-40 (1985) (referring
to the effort that citizen enforcement groups had to expend gaining credibility and legiti-
macy as enforcers); Harold J. Krent, Fragmenting the Unitary Executive: Congressional
Delegations of Administrative Authority Outside the Federal Government, 85 NW. U. L.
REV. 62, 70, 95-96 (1990); Stewart, supra note 12, at 679 (arguing that citizen enforcement
by narrow issue groups may create more problems than they were designed to solve).
2000] CONTRACTING STATE 199
to be the product of explicit contracting between agencies and stake-
holders. Indeed, two of the dominant theories (public interest and
civic republicanism) would affirmatively reject such a proposal as
enabling government to abdicate its role, and a third (interest repre-
sentation) advocates procedural reforms that would structure the po-
litical process without presumably allowing it to devolve into explicit
contracts.
182
For most commentators, the pursuit of contractual regu-
lation would be fundamentally undemocratic, particularly if agencies
experimented with it under the guise of their enforcement discretion
without explicit authorization by Congress.
183
Even when Congress
approves it, however, contractual regulation attracts considerable
criticism. A move to contract may prove simply implausible in a po-
litical culture historically intolerant of all things corporatist.
184
The debate over regulatory negotiation provides a case in point. A
number of commentators object to reg-neg on the theory that it en-
courages the convening agency to abdicate its responsibility for im-
plementing congressional intent.
185
One commentator asserts that
“the principles, theory, and practice of negotiated rulemaking subtly
subvert the basic, underlying concepts of American administrative
law.”
186
In this view, regulation requires an authoritative decision
maker, while contract reduces the agency to a negotiating partner.
Conceptually, the two are mutually exclusive.
2. Ousting Public Law Norms
For some, contractual approaches to regulation might be objec-
tionable because they “oust” public norms in favor of private ones.
Processes like reg-neg and Project XL seem to prioritize the satisfac-
tion of the immediate parties over satisfaction of the “public interest”
(however loosely defined) by, say, elevating the importance of reach-
182. In its description of the legislative and bureaucratic process, public choice theory
seems most compatible with a view of regulation as de facto contractual, and yet, public
choice scholars tend to shy away from normative prescriptions. Moreover, only a minority
of public choice scholars are self-consciously normative, and when they are, they typically
advocate deregulation. See, e.g., ANDREI SHLEIFER & ROBERT W. VISHNY, THE GRABBING
HAND 3-5 (1998) (claiming that the premise of the “grabbing hand” approach is that gov-
ernment control of economic activity is itself the fundamental problem).
183. See Bradford Mank, The Environmental Protection Agency’s Project XL and Other
Regulatory Reform Initiatives: The Need for Legislative Authorization, 25 ECOLOGY L.Q. 1
(1998).
184. On the other hand, there is certainly precedent for peak -level negotiations among
interest groups resulting in enforceable bargainsone need only look to the history of col-
lective bargaining in labor law.
185. See, e.g., Coglianese, supra note 151, at 1334-37 (questioning the perceived ability
of reg-negs to limit delays and conflicts in the regulatory process); Susan Rose -Ackerman,
American Administrative Law Under Siege: Is Germany a Model?, 107 HARV. L. REV. 1279,
1281 (1994) (claiming that regulatory negotiation is “inadequate if one accepts [a] basic
commitment to . . . the democratic legitimacy of the administrative process”).
186. Funk, supra note 151, at 1356.
200 FLORIDA STATE UNIVERSITY LAW REVIEW [Vol. 28:155
ing consensus over other values that the median voter or average
consumer might care about (such as the stringency of a health or
safety standard or the speed of its implementation). One might also
argue that contractual approaches deprive the courts of opportunities
for adjudication by settling important matters of public policy pri-
vately. This chargethat the “privatization” of decisionmaking de-
prives a democratic society of the norm-articulating function of judi-
cial decisionshas been leveled frequently at both alternative dis-
pute resolution as a means of settling civil suits and at settlement in
general, but it applies equally, and perhaps more potently, to public
policy decisions normally made by government agencies.
187
Recall for example, that parties in a regulatory negotiation com-
mit, as a condition of participation, not to challenge the consensus
rule. If a significant percentage of rules were produced this way,
courts might lose their critical role in protecting and advancing,
through review of agency decisionmaking, the public policy articu-
lated in regulations. This could deprive the public of a check on the
agency’s interpretation of its delegated authority, affording courts
fewer opportunities to weigh in on the meaning of statutes.
188
In this view then, a process like regulatory negotiation co-opts the
agency: the agency outsources its regulatory responsibility to stake-
holders that make deals to serve their interests, which the agency
then promulgates and defends in the form of final rules. While the
potential for reg-neg to reduce the risk of legal challenge might be a
prized benefit for its fans, to critics it simply means that rulemak-
ingan already opaque process to the average persongets driven
further underground. In this vein one might argue that with a rate of
legal challenge for conventionally developed rules hovering between
187. This concern surfaces frequently as a criticism of alternative dispute resolution
(ADR) and as the reason for judicial reluctance to enforce arbitration agreements. See, e.g.,
1 RICHARD L. ABEL ET AL., THE POLITICS OF INFORMAL JUSTICE: THE AMERICAN
EXPERIENCE (Richard L. Abel ed., 1982); Owen M. Fiss, Against Settlement, 93 YALE L.J.
1073 (1984); David Luban, Settlements and the Erosion of the Public Realm, 83 GEO. L.J.
2619, 2622-25 (1995); see also Edward Brunet, Questioning the Validity of Alternative Dis-
pute Resolution, 62 TUL. L. REV. 1, 19-21 (1987) (arguing that conventional litigation
should be viewed as a public good and that litigation offers benefits to third parties, such
as written opinions to guide future behavior); G. Richard Shell, ERISA and Other Federal
Employment Statutes: When Is Commercial Arbitration an “Adequate Substitute” for the
Courts?, 68 TEX. L. REV. 509, 517, 566-69 (1990) (describing mandatory ADR in employ-
ment law and the loss of Title VII claims in terms of a loss of “public value” articulation by
courts).
188. Scholars have made a similar argument about the rise of judicial decisionmaking
without publishing reasons. See Mitu Gulati & C.M.A. McCauliff, On Not Making Law,
LAW & CONTEMP. PROBS., Summer 1998, at 157. “The failure to write and publish an opin-
ion deprives the system of the many positive externalities created when a case is decided
by a published opinion that gives reasons.” Id. at 175. Of course, most regulations are
never challenged and subjected to judicial review. This could cut either for or against the
argument that more negotiated rules would meaningfully undermine the articulation of
public norms.
2000] CONTRACTING STATE 201
twenty-five and thirty-five percent, the rulemaking process may not
be “ossified” enough.
189
Further reducing litigation would remove an
important check on bureaucratic decisionmaking.
The complaint about “ouster” is reminiscent of capture theory and
resonates with the public choice account of the legislative and bu-
reaucratic process. Although negotiation has always characterized
the regulatory process, it was precisely the fear that informal deals
were subverting the public interest that motivated the procedural re-
form of agency process during the sixties and seventies. Critics thus
view the embrace of negotiation, and presumably enforceable regula-
tory contracts of all kinds, as, at best, a romantic and misguided en-
terprise, and at worst a naked power grab by well-financed repeat
players.
V. CONTRACT AS AN ACCOUNTABILITY MECHANISM
Thus, all of the contractual examples discussed thus far, whether
contracts to provide services or perform functions of regulatory con-
tracts, engender considerable opposition for a variety of reasons. Ex-
tensive contracting out poses significant contractual design chal-
lenges, enables government to avoid constitutional scrutiny through
delegation and may, in at least some circumstances, be viewed as in-
compatible with liberal democratic principles. In addition, contract-
ing out may disempower third-party beneficiaries who enjoy few
rights of participation in a privately controlled decisionmaking proc-
ess. Finally, widespread contracting out may weaken both Congress
and the executive branch by diffusing power so effectively as to im-
pede monitoring and supervision, while simultaneously burdening
the judiciary with appeals for third-party beneficiary rights of action
and demands for judicial review of contract validity. This will force
courts to wrestle with a potentially uncomfortable convergence of
public and private law. Like contracts to perform functions or provide
services, regulatory contracts also present drafting and technical de-
sign challenges and in some cases allow agencies to “abdicate” regu-
latory responsibility. These contracts may also increase the burden
on the judiciary. In particular, courts will need to reconcile contract
principles of interpretation with administrative law principles of def-
erence.
Despite posing considerable cause for concern, contractual in-
struments also represent potentially useful accountability instru-
ments. Conceivably, public-private contracts could function not only
as mechanisms for delivering social services or effecting regulatory
purposes, but as vehicles for achieving public law values, such as
189. But cf. Thomas O. McGarity, Some Thoughts on “Deossifying” the Rulemaking
Process, 41 DUKE L.J. 1385, 1385 (1992) (arguing that rulemaking has become ossified).
202 FLORIDA STATE UNIVERSITY LAW REVIEW [Vol. 28:155
fairness, openness, and accountability. Contracts themselves might
do more work as enforceable agreements.
190
Provider contracts could
equip agencies with more effective enforcement tools. In the nursing
home context, for example, greater specificity of terms, graduated
penalties, and oversight by a “contract manager” employed by the
agency might help agencies to oversee quality of care. Indeed, trends
point in this direction. Recent reforms in the nursing home context
have put a greater variety of enforcement tools at government’s dis-
posal.
191
Contracts could also require private homes to observe minimal
administrative procedures such as notice and hearing requirements,
which might help to eradicate the most arbitrary decisions and slow
the pace of others. Given legitimate fears about lax government en-
forcement, contracts could go farther still by conferring explicitly
upon patients third-party beneficiary rights that would allow con-
sumers to sue when government monitoring failed.
192
In addition to
these traditional measures, contracts could be instruments for diver-
sifying sources of oversight. For example, a contract could establish
an ombudsman to represent nursing home residents, or it could de-
mand that nursing homes submit to periodic review by a community
oversight committee.
193
Contracts could help to provide accountability in the Medicaid
managed care context as well. As major and growing purchasers of
care, states will soon be in a position to drive demand for NCQA ac-
creditation of MCOs.
194
States could require by contract that MCOs
190. Courts adjudicate disputes over payment, withdrawal from a program, or any
other matter arising within the agency-provider relationship on principles of contract law.
See Elias S. Cohen, Legislative and Educational Alternatives to a Judicial Remedy for the
Transfer Trauma Dilemma, 11 AM. J.L. & MED. 405, 418 (1986) (summarizing three fed-
eral cases involving voluntary withdrawal from Medicaid provider and noting that these
types of cases turn on the issue of contractual relationship between the state agency and
provider).
191. See Health Care Fin. Admin., supra note 90.
192. Some state statutes and judicial decisions have recognized private rights of action
to enforce state licensure laws in the context of nursing homes. See Kinney, supra note 26,
at 68 n.147 (citing SANDRA H. JOHNSON ET AL., NURSING HOMES AND THE LAW: STATE
REGULATION AND PRIVATE LITIGATION §§ 1-21 to 1-28 (1985)); see also Smith v. Heckler,
747 F.2d 583 (10th Cir. 1984) (holding in a class action suit that the HHS Secretary had
violated the Medicaid Act by not informing herself as to whether facilities receiving federal
money satisfied federal requirements).
193. Indeed, third-party oversight by either family members of residents or community
groups already seems to be a crucial ingredient in the quality of nursing home care. Com-
munity interest and concern is the single most important reason why small and rural nurs-
ing homes have the best reputations for high quality of care. Community groups that sup-
port nursing home residents have organized across the country. See Butler, supra note 26,
at 1377.
194. “State and local governments spend about 45% of the total health care purchasing
dollars. Public purchasers, with their enormous purchasing power and their regulatory au-
thority over those from whom they purchase health care, have the potential to drive the
market in health care.” CAREN GINSBERG, ACADEMY FOR HEALTH SERVS. & HEALTH
2000] CONTRACTING STATE 203
diversify the providers they include in their provider networks. By
demanding as a condition of the contract that MCOs include tradi-
tionally public health agencies as providers, states could introduce a
quality benchmark for private providers, who may be less familiar
with the vulnerable Medicaid population and may need to develop
new methodologies and criteria for evaluating the sufficiency of their
care.
195
And although the transition to managed care may initially
overwhelm state agencies, many states appear to be adapting to the
new regime by developing model contracts.
196
Today, the length and detail of provider contracts varies across
states, but there is a notable trend toward both detailed standards
and diversification of penalties.
197
Even relatively short provider con-
tracts, those that simply regurgitate federal and state Medicaid
law,
198
extend federal and state regulations to private providers. As a
result, they could enable government agencies to monitor quality, as
well as control fraudulent claims. Some states now employ contract
managers to monitor state contracts with MCOs; California recently
created a state department of managed care.
199
The contracts them-
selves could constitute crucial accountability mechanisms, enabling
state agencies to demand submission to independent third-party
oversight, private accreditation, and insurance requirements, among
other things. Contracts might thus serve as a means of enlisting ad-
POLICY, IN PURSUIT OF VALUE : INNOVATIVE STATE /MEDICAID PURCHASING STRATEGIES 3
(State Initiatives in Health Care Reform Monograph/Memoranda No. 41, 1997). According
to another report, federal funds constitute 57% of all funds flowing to MCOs. See
SCHNEIDER, supra note 125, at 17, http://www.kff.org/content/archive/2102. In addition to
relying on commercial standards of quality, some states “piggyback” on state insurance
regulators to certify financial solvency of MCOs and on private accreditors to certify the
quality of the institutions’ clinical standards of care. See Interview with Sharon Connors,
supra note 122.
195. See Perkins & Olson, supra note 121, at 22.
196. See NEGOTIATING THE NEW HEALTH SYSTEM, supra note 112 (reviewing variety of
state contracts and noting trend toward larger and more complex contracts),
http://www.gwumc.edu/chpr/overview/overview.htm.
197. Although some contracts appear to be relatively short (eight pages in Massachu-
setts, for example) others contain extremely detailed provisions. See id.
198. Letter from Gary Abrahams, Dir. of Reimbursement, Mass. Extended Care Fed’n,
to Author (Aug. 18, 1999) (on file with the Florida State University Law Review).
199. Legislation establishing California’s Department of Managed Care (DMC) came
into effect on January 1, 2000, and the DMC is scheduled to become operative by July 1,
2000. The DMC will regulate all MCOs, and not just those relevant to Medicaid managed
care. See California Dep’t of Managed Care, at http://www.dmc.ca.gov/library/lawregs/
knox-keene/1999/assembly/ab78.asp (visited Oct. 2, 2000). Other states have adopted dif-
ferent institutional reforms. For example, in Ohio the Bureau of Managed Health Care
(BMHC) within the Ohio Department of Human Services is responsible for the administra-
tion of the Ohio Medicaid managed care program. See Medicaid Managed Care Program, at
http://www.state.oh.us/odjfs/ohp/managed.stm (visited Oct.2, 2000). Its responsibilities in-
clude monitoring the quality of, access to, and performance of managed health care plans.
See Ohio Dep’t of Job & Family Servs., Bureau of Managed Health Care, at http://www.
state.oh.us/odjfs/ohp/bmhc (visited Oct. 2, 2000).
204 FLORIDA STATE UNIVERSITY LAW REVIEW [Vol. 28:155
ditional nongovernmental entities such as community groups and pa-
tient advocates to provide accountability.
200
For example, Wisconsin has embarked on a Medicaid managed
care program which one commentator described as “built on con-
tracts” between the state Medicaid administrator, MCOs, communi-
ties, public health organizations, and consumer groups.
201
Exercising
its power as purchaser, the agency “encourages MCOs to utilize
community groups, public health units, and schools” to provide
care,
202
and these commitments are reflected in formal agreements.
203
Among other things, the agreements provide for HMO advocates to
represent patients and coordinate activity with community coali-
tions.
204
Similarly, the state Medicaid agency in Massachusetts has
developed a “customer advisory committee” to represent the popula-
tions served by each of their benefit plans.
205
Thus, there are oppor-
tunities for fostering accountability through a combination of con-
tractual, organizational, and market-based mechanisms.
The prison context presents equally significant opportunities for
contract to help provide accountability. The already powerful pres-
ence of private standard setting, for example, could be further ex-
ploited through contract. States could require compliance with both
procedural and substantive standards that might otherwise be inap-
plicable or unenforceable against private providers.
206
The model con-
tract for private prison management drafted by the Texas Depart-
ment of Criminal Justice (TDCJ) demands, for example, that contrac-
tors comply with constitutional, federal, state, and private standards,
including those established by the American Correctional Association
200. Again, the devolution of welfare reform offers a useful analogue. Although welfare
“privatization” could cut costs and improve service delivery, we might also be concerned
that states will avoid responsibility for cutting welfare rolls by shifting blame to private ac-
tors. Resorting to traditional constraints, one could argue that private parties ought to be
considered “state actors” when they administer benefits or, instead, seek to invalidate
delegations of power to them. See Kennedy, supra note 31, at 283-85 (applying the balanc-
ing test used in Mathews v. Eldridge, 424 U.S. 319, 334-35 (1976), and arguing that gov-
ernment interest is minimized where the cost of adding procedure falls to private contrac-
tors). Given current state action doctrine, these efforts will likely prove fruitless or achieve
only minimal due process protections. Again, however, the contractual mechanisms them-
selves could present opportunities for structuring the public-private arrangement. Con-
tracts could require private companies to retain professional social workers, for example.
Contracts, speculatively, could enable alliances to develop among private companies, pro-
fessional groups, and poverty advocates.
201. See Louise G. Trubek, The Health Care Puzzle: Creating Coverage for Low-Wage
Workers and Their Families, in HARD LABOR: WOMEN AND WORK IN THE POST-WELFARE
ERA, supra note 106, at 143, 144-45.
202. Id.
203. See id. at 145.
204. Advocates are often licensed health care professionals. See id.
205. See GINSBERG, supra note 194, at 9.
206. See Michael Keating, Jr., Public over Private: Monitoring the Performance of Pri-
vately Operated Prisons and Jails, in PRIVATE PRISONS AND THE PUBLIC INTEREST, supra
73, at 138-41.
2000] CONTRACTING STATE 205
(ACA) and the National Commission of Correctional Health Care
Standards.
207
Contractors must certify that training provided to per-
sonnel is equal to that for state employees,
208
and they must meet
numerous performance standards concerning security, meals, and
education.
209
The model contract states, among other things, that the contractor
shall “continually conduct self-monitoring, utilizing a comprehensive
self-monitoring plan approved by TDCJ.”
210
This is equivalent to re-
quiring a company to adopt a significant management reform. The
contract also requires that private contractors establish performance
measures for rehabilitative programs and develop a system to assess
achievement and outcomes. State governments could also make
mandatory disclosure a contractual term,
211
requiring private con-
tractors to publish statistics on inmate graduation from training or
rehabilitation programs, or rates of illness or recidivism.
In addition, the contractor must attain and maintain ACA ac-
creditation within eighteen months of commencement.
212
Throughout
its history the ACA has fostered professionalism in prison admini-
stration through the development of standards and promoted pro-
gressive reforms such as rehabilitation.
213
ACA standards govern
most aspects of prison operationincluding security and control, food
service, sanitation and hygiene, medical and health care, inmate
rights, work programs, educational programs, recreational activities,
library services, records, and personnel issuesand they are typi-
207. See Texas Department of Criminal Justice, Purchasing and Leases Department,
Contracts Branch, Request for Proposal: Private Prison, http://www.tdcj.state.tx.us/
finance/purch&lease/finpurch-conad.htm (last visited Nov. 14, 2000) (example of a service
for a private prison) [hereinafter Texas Model Contract].
208. See id. at 12 (stating employees must be trained pursuant to TDCJ training re-
quirements).
209. See id. at 12, 15, 18 (setting forth standards for security, meals, and education, re-
spectively). The contract contains specifications for education, see id. at 32 (requiring,
among other things, a 65% pass rate for GED); vocational training, see id. ex. J.6, at 86
(mandating that 20% of offender population be enrolled in and attend vocational training);
and even the books in the library, see id. at 25-26 (specifying percentages of different
types).
210. Id. at 45.
211. See Paul R. Kleindorfer & Eric W. Orts, Informational Regulation of Environ-
mental Risks, 18 RISK ANALYSIS 155, 156-57 (1998) (discussing disclosure in informational
regulatory schemes); Richard C. Rich et al., “Indirect Regulation” of Environmental Haz-
ards Through the Provision of Information to the Public: The Case of SARA, Title III, 21
POLY STUD. J. 16, 31 (1993) (suggesting proactive risk communication strategy for envi-
ronmental hazards). Federal statutes such as the Emergency Planning and Community
Right-to-Know Act of 1986, 42 U.S.C. §§ 11001-11050 (1994), and state initiatives such as
California’s Proposition 65, passed at the November 4, 1986, general election and imple-
mented as the Safe Drinking Water and Toxic Enforcement Act of 1986, Cal. Health &
Safety Code §§ 25249.5-.13 (West 1998), require industry to disclose use of toxic chemicals.
212. See Texas Model Contract, supra note 207, at 46.
213. See FEELEY & RUBIN, supra note 133, at 163.
206 FLORIDA STATE UNIVERSITY LAW REVIEW [Vol. 28:155
cally more demanding than state or federal requirements.
214
By re-
quiring compliance with ACA standards, the state relies, in part, on
another private actor to help ensure that contractors fulfill their ob-
ligations.
The model contract also requires contractors to carry insurance
for up to $2 million per incident and $5 million per year for civil
rights liability in addition to worker’s compensation insurance. It
further stipulates the minimal rating for the insurers.
215
It requires
contractors to disclose all parties with a substantial interest in the
proposal, presumably in an effort to surface conflicts of interest.
216
The contract also provides for inspection authority, access to records,
and entry to the facility at any time. TDCJ may terminate contracts
for a variety of reasons, including any material failure to comply with
any covenant, condition, agreement, or TDCJ policy. TDCJ’s reme-
dies for the contractor’s breach are extensive, but the contractor’s
sole remedy for TDCJ’s breach is payment for services furnished.
217
Finally, although all contract changes must be mutually agreed
upon, the contract authorizes TDCJ to unilaterally amend the terms
when “judicial decisions, settlement agreements, statutes, regula-
tions, rules and decisions of federal and state courts and governing
agencies require changes or amendments” to the contract.
218
Finally, these contracts could also facilitate third-party participa-
tion in oversight by requiring independent monitoring or auditing of
prisons by certified professionals. They might enlist the help of inde-
pendent prisoners’ rights groups by granting them standing to sue
for violations of any contractual terms.
219
Clearly, absent enforcement, the mere existence of these detailed
provisions offers little assurance of accountability. And admittedly,
many provisions leave considerable room for interpretation, as does
the description of the limited situations in which the personnel may
use force to subdue prisoners.
220
Nonetheless, the contract presents
214. See Hart et al., supra note 80, at 1149. Although not dispositive, compliance with
ACA standards may also help private firms defend against litigation under 42 U.S.C.
§ 1983. Federal courts have relied on compliance with ACA standards as an indication of
the acceptability of prison conditions. See FEELEY & RUBIN, supra note 133, at 163. In the
prison reform cases of the 1960s and 1970s, the ACA manual became a “leading resource”
for federal courts. Id. at 163, citing Judge Henley’s ruling in Holt v. Sarver, 309 F. Supp.
362 (E.D. Ark. 1970), which addresses all of the issues in the manual and incorporates
many of its standards.
215. See Texas Model Contract, supra note 207, at 58-59.
216. See id. at 62.
217. See id. at 68.
218. Id.
219. Such contracts may already be a source of third-party beneficiary rights. See
Owens v. Haas, 601 F.2d 1242, 1250-51 (2d Cir. 1979) (holding that a federal prisoner
benefiting from a contract between the federal government and Nassau County may sue
under the contract).
220. See Texas Model Contract, supra note 207, at 45.
2000] CONTRACTING STATE 207
an opportunity for TDCJ to regulate contractors very extensively and
to demand compliance with standards that even government facili-
ties may not meet. Moreover, the terms appear favorable to the
agency and do not seem to undermine its concurrent regulatory au-
thority over the contractor. Whether the agency’s interpretations of
contractual terms will receive the deference they would receive were
they regulations, however, remains to be seen.
Regulatory contracts may represent an equally potent instrument
of accountability under the right conditions. Recall that reg-neg, Pro-
ject XL, and the HCP process all conform to requirements of open-
ness and balanced representation. These provide access to a variety
of stakeholders, including community groups, experts, nonprofit or-
ganizations, and issue organizations.
221
They also force parties to
commit their agreements to writing, which not only serves as a dis-
closure mechanism but as a potential monitoring device as well.
Permits, plans, and project agreements are accessible to third-party
watchdogs, who might help to oversee compliance with their terms.
Regulatory contracting might also enable agencies to extend their
influence. Rather than weakening agencies, then, contracts may be
instruments of strength. Within their enforcement discretion, or un-
der the direction of Congress, agencies might strike covenants with
regulated entities in which they trade flexibility for commitments not
mandated by legislation or regulationhardly a new idea, given that
agencies already do this via settlement.
222
This extended reach is only
possible where parties can prioritize and trade interests, as they can
when negotiating consensus rules, Project XL Agreements, HCPs,
and SEPs.
VI. THE UNCOMFORTABLE INTERFACE OF
PUBLIC LAW NORMS AND PRIVATE LAW PRINCIPLES
Although the service provision and regulatory contexts differ in
important ways, the use of contract in both settings raises significant
technical, conceptual, and doctrinal problems. Both public-private
service contracts and regulatory contracts force an uncomfortable in-
terface between public law notions of deference to agency action and
private law principles of contract interpretation. The question is how
to adapt the law of contract to contexts in which government acts in
both a regulatory and a contractual capacity at the same time. From
a traditional administrative law perspective, contractual relation-
ships between public and private actors might undermine agency au-
221. See Freeman, supra note 151, at 36-57 (describing the reg-neg and XL convening
processes).
222. See, e.g., Rich Vision Centers, Inc. v. Board of Medical Exam’rs, 144 Cal. App. 3d
110 (1983) (holding that an agency’s authority to settle disputes was implicitly authorized
by statute).
208 FLORIDA STATE UNIVERSITY LAW REVIEW [Vol. 28:155
thority and alter prevailing conceptions of judicial deference to
agency action. Courts may not accord agencies deference in contract
interpretation, nor might they permit agencies unilaterally to amend
terms as they might regulations. Agencies could presumably avoid
these difficulties by promulgating contracts as regulations in order to
recapture the deference they might otherwise lose, or negotiate only
short-term contracts, obviating the need to incorporate them as regu-
lations. But these procedures would encumber and rigidify a more
flexible contracting process, perhaps undermining some of the bene-
fits of contracting with private parties.
Courts have struggled with the conflict between government as
regulator and government as contractor, drawing sharp lines be-
tween the two. They have consistently approached government’s use
of contract by categorizing the nature of the government intervention
as either regulatory or contractual and according the government
deference when it acts in its regulatory capacity. In the procurement
context, for example, where government seems to act most like a pri-
vate purchaser, judicial interpretation nonetheless typically works to
the benefit of government. Even when agencies do not insert termi-
nation-for-convenience clauses in federal procurement contracts,
courts imply them. When agencies do insert them, courts treat such
clauses as instances of agency discretion, and they defer.
223
Experiments with regulatory contract highlight the problems that
arise when agencies act as both regulators and contractors. Experi-
ence with reg-neg, Project XL, habitat conservation plans, and the
like suggests that agencies do act in more than one mode simultane-
ously. In these contexts, agencies set default rules, foster coopera-
tion, muster credible threats, and monitor performance, but they
must also bargain, make deals, and keep their word. Although these
roles need not conflict, at times they will, and the prevailing theories
of administrative law do not adequately account for them or explore
the extent to which they may be compatible or incompatible.
224
Courts currently appear reluctant to bind agencies to their regula-
tory agreements with private stakeholders. In USA Group Loan Ser-
vices v. Riley,
225
the only appellate case reviewing a negotiated rule,
223. See Hadfield, supra note 43, at 492-93.
224. Not surprisingly, agencies currently appear confused over how to mediate be-
tween these very different roles. Consider regulatory negotiation: The agency’s participa-
tion puts it in the awkward position of being asked to essentially preapprove tentative
agreements when it is required to provide public comment periods and perform internal
review before approval can be given. The agency is always constrained from participating
in a negotiation as an equal. Thus, the agency finds itself having to indicate which out-
comes would be acceptable without compromising its ultimate authority to alter its posi-
tion on the deal should political winds change or the formal comment period turn up an-
ticipated problems with the proposed rule. See generally Freeman, supra note 151, at 83-
96; Coglianese, supra note 151, at 1322-26.
225. 82 F.3d 708 (7th Cir. 1996).
2000] CONTRACTING STATE 209
the Seventh Circuit held that the promise to bargain in good faith is
not enforceable under the NRA and that the agency may depart from
the consensus when promulgating the rule.
226
The Court expressed
concern that to hold otherwise would allow the agency to abdicate its
responsibility for rulemaking.
227
However, if contract emerges as an important regulatory instru-
ment, courts will wrestle regularly with these matters, as litigants
press for assurances that government cannot simply renege at will. If
a government agency fails to perform its contractual obligations, ei-
ther because the responsible agency changes its mind or because an-
other agency’s decision renders performance impossible or because
Congress subsequently reverses an agency’s decision, should the gov-
ernment be liable for breach? And if so, what is the appropriate
measure of damages?
228
This question has arisen in Contracts Clause
jurisprudence involving state governments’ breach of their contracts
with private parties, as well as in zoning and development decisions
involving local government, but there is a relative dearth of judicial
guidance on the federal government’s obligations when it contracts
with private parties. Recently, however, the Supreme Court signaled
a new willingness to hold government liable for breach.
In United States v. Winstar Corp.,
229
the Court found the federal
government liable for breach
230
of what the plurality called a “risk-
shifting agreement”
231
between the Federal Home Loan Bank Board
and three savings-and-loan thrifts. The agreement had allowed
healthy S&Ls to use a favorable accounting device for valuing failing
S&Ls as an inducement to the healthy S&Ls to acquire them.
232
As
the S&L crisis worsened, however, Congress reneged on the agree-
ments by passing the Financial Institutions Reform, Recovery, and
Enforcement Act of 1989 (FIRREA),
233
which imposed more stringent
financial requirements on healthy S&Ls, eliminating the favorable
accounting incentive.
234
In a plurality opinion that opens a doctrinal
Pandora’s box, the Court upheld the Federal Circuit’s decision that
the government had breached its contracts with the S&Ls and was
liable for damages.
235
226. See id. at 714-15.
227. See id.
228. See Hadfield, supra note 43, at 492-93 (arguing that in cases of government
breach of “regulatory” contracts, government should be liable only for reliance rather than
expectation damages).
229. 518 U.S. 839 (1996).
230. See id. at 910.
231. Id. at 881.
232. See id. at 847-56. The device allowed favorable valuations for “supervisory good-
will” of the acquired S&Ls. Id. at 849.
233. Pub. L. No. 101-73, 103 Stat. 183.
234. See Winstar Corp., 518 U.S. at 856-57.
235. See id. at 910.
210 FLORIDA STATE UNIVERSITY LAW REVIEW [Vol. 28:155
The matter of government breach has taken shape then largely in
the shadow of the Contracts Clause,
236
which forbids states from im-
pairing private rights of contract.
237
As with the demise of substan-
tive due process in the wake of Lochner v. New York,
238
the Contracts
Clause’s potentially restrictive effects on government power subsided
in the 1930s, as state governments began to successfully avail them-
selves of two affirmative defenses to actions for breach: the sovereign
acts doctrine and the unmistakability defense.
239
These are the two
defenses that the plurality merged in Winstar and that commenta-
tors fear will amount to a net loss in government protection from
suits for breach.
240
The unmistakability defense embodies the idea that:
[w]ithout regard to its source, sovereign power, even when unexer-
cised, is an enduring presence that governs all contracts subject to
the sovereign’s jurisdiction, and will remain intact unless surren-
dered in unmistakable terms. Therefore, contractual arrange-
ments, including those to which a sovereign itself is a party, “re-
main subject to subsequent legislation” by the sovereign.
241
In addition to unmistakability, the federal government has histori-
cally been able to afford itself of the sovereign acts doctrine as a de-
fense to claims for breach.
242
The doctrine has its roots in cases de-
cided by the Court of Claims in 1865.
243
Until Winstar the first and
only application of the sovereign acts defense by the Supreme Court
was in Horowitz v. United States.
244
The plurality in Winstar rejected
the unmistakability defense and all but merged the sovereign acts
236. U.S. CONST. art. I, § 10, cl. 1.
237. See id.
238. 198 U.S. 45 (1905). The death knell was sounded in West Coast Hotel Co. v. Par-
rish, 300 U.S. 379, 392-93 (1937).
239. For a useful history of the origins of the two doctrines, and an explanation of the
difference between them, see Graf, supra note 57, at 207-19.
240. Although the Contracts Clause does not apply to the federal government, the Su-
preme Court had, in the 1980s, extended the unmistakability doctrine to cases involving
regulatory action by the federal government. See Bowen v. Public Agencies Opposed to Soc.
Sec. Entrapment, 477 U.S. 41, 52 (1986); Michael P. Malloy, When You Wish upon Winstar:
Contract Analysis and the Future of Regulatory Action, 42 ST. LOUIS U. L.J. 409, 421-22
(1998); Joshua I. Schwartz, Assembling Winstar: Triumph of the Ideal of Congruence in
Government Contracts Law?, 26 PUB. CONT. L.J. 481, 500 (1997); Thomas J. Gilliam, Jr.,
Note, Contracting with the United States in Its Role as Regulator: Striking a Bargain with
an Equitable Sovereign or Capricious Siren?, 18 MISS. C. L. REV. 247, 264-69 (1998). These
defenses are all the more necessary from the government’s perspective because the do c-
trine of sovereign immunity does not immunize the federal government from claims for
breach of contract.
241. Bowen, 477 U.S. at 52 (citation omitted) (quoting Merrion v. Jicarilla Apache
Tribe, 455 U.S. 130, 147 (1982)).
242. See Malloy, supra note 240, at 425.
243. See id. at 427.
244. 267 U.S. 458 (1925); see also Gilliam, supra note 240, at 273 (citing Horowitz v.
United States, 267 U.S. 458, 461 (1925)); Malloy, supra note 240, at 427.
2000] CONTRACTING STATE 211
and unmistakability defenses, arguably limiting their applicability in
future cases.
245
Winstar has breathed new life into arguments that the govern-
ment ought to be vulnerable to breach of contract claims when it
makes regulatory contracts on which it subsequently reneges. For
some commentators, the case signals a shift away from judicial rec-
ognition of the government’s special sovereign status, and toward
treating government as if it were any private contracting party.
246
Before Winstar, it was safe to say that in cases alleging govern-
ment breach of contract, courts granted considerable deference to
both state and federal government defendants because of their sover-
eign status. Although there remain limitations on state governments’
freedom to breach their contracts for purely self-interested reasons,
these limits are fairly minimal and are reserved for what seem like
egregious cases of reneging.
247
When states can satisfy courts that
their breach is motivated by public-oriented reasons that fall within
the legitimate exercise of their police power, they prevail. Now, ironi-
cally (in light of the fact that the Contracts Clause applies only to the
states), state governments may well have more room to maneuver
than the federal government. The post-Winstar case law on suits
against governments for breach could have an enormous impact on
the future of regulatory contracting. In the wake of Winstar, private
parties may be encouraged to enter into contracts with government,
but critics may grow more apprehensive about their antidemocratic
potential.
In addition to this jurisprudence, local government law might con-
ceivably be a source of guidance on how courts would treat regulatory
contracts between government and private actors, because land use
regulation is replete with public-private bargains. This jurisprudence
is ad hoc, at best, however. The adjudication of government-private
development agreements or contingent zoning cases consists of a mo-
rass of disparate decisions that, in the end, amount to context-
specific judicial assessments of “reasonableness.”
248
More promising
are the attempts by scholars like Judith Wegner and Carol Rose to
shape that jurisprudence with state and local governments’ dual and
inseparable roles in mind and to develop standards by which to as-
sess whether contractual regulation is inclusive, rational, and fair.
249
This kind of approach may be a useful beginning point for reconceiv-
245. See United States v. Winstar Corp., 518 U.S. 839, 860, 864, 868 (1996).
246. See Gilliam, supra note 240, at 272.
247. See USA Group Loan Servs. v. Riley, 82 F.3d 703, 714-15 (7th Cir. 1996).
248. See Judith Welch Wegner, Utopian Visions: Cooperation Without Conflicts in Pub-
lic/Private Ventures, 31 SANTA CLARA L. REV. 313, 328-31 (1991).
249. See id. at 328-43; see also Rose, supra note 179, at 882-903.
212 FLORIDA STATE UNIVERSITY LAW REVIEW [Vol. 28:155
ing the federal government’s dual roles as well, in the wake of Win-
star.
VII. CONCLUSION
The rise of contract as an instrument of service and benefit provi-
sion and as an instrument of regulation will place great pressure on
contractual design and contractual remedies. It will challenge agen-
cies, courts, and legislatures alike to deal with new blends of regula-
tion and contract. Constructing a contractual regime to produce
meaningful accountability will require a significant attitudinal shift
on the part of agencies, which would need to play both the facilitative
role of contracting parties and the authoritative role of regulators.
Government agencies need to view contractual instruments as full-
blown accountability mechanisms designed to monitor quality, pro-
vide access to decisionmaking, and ensure procedural fairness, not
just as accounting tools for monitoring the award of huge sums of
money or occasional instances of discretion designed to provide relief
from rigid regulatory requirements.
For contracts to be meaningful accountability mechanisms, how-
ever, agencies must develop and adapt their monitoring capacity,
which requires both adequate funding and a shift in management
priorities.
250
Agencies require sufficient resources to hire and train
personnel in contract management, but they must also shift their
contract management priorities from preventing fraud and waste to
overseeing quality and ensuring responsiveness to beneficiary com-
plaints. To accomplish this may require organizational changes, such
as centralizing authority for contract management in a single man-
ager or dividing contracts among a small group of coordinated man-
agers who answer to senior agency staff.
However, whether public-private contracts will ultimately under-
mine or enhance accountability will depend on more than just the
adaptability of government agencies. Agencies respond, after all, to
the incentives provided by Congress, the judiciary, and the Presi-
dent. Thus the fate of contract will depend significantly upon
whether legislators have the political will to demand agency over-
sight and whether they help to create the incentives necessary to
produce it. For example, if agency officials must account to congres-
sional committees only for fraud and abuse, they will continue to
marshal their resources to prevent it, ignoring the other substantive
250. See SARA ROSENBAUM ET AL., GEORGE WASHINGTON UNIV. MED. CTR., AN
EVALUATION OF CONTRACTS BETWEEN STATE MEDICAID AGENCIES AND MANAGED CARE
ORGANIZATIONS FOR THE PREVENTION AND TREATMENT OF MENTAL ILLNESS AND
SUBSTANCE ABUSE DISORDERS 21-22 (1997) (noting the need for Medicaid agencies to sup-
plement their internal analytic capabilities through agreements with other state agencies
and institutions specializing in data analysis).
2000] CONTRACTING STATE 213
features of their contracts with private providers. If Congress wishes
to devolve and diffuse decisionmaking power, and to disarm agencies
by shrinking their budgets, contract could indeed help to incapacitate
the state. Even without drastic measures, Congress may frustrate
the accountability-enhancing potential of contract by refusing to ex-
plicitly provide private rights of action in legislation or by failing to
enable agencies to insert third-party beneficiary rights to sue in their
contracts with private providers. By simply not recognizing the im-
portant role that agencies can play as “contractual partners” with
private parties, Congress, the courts, and even the President may ob-
struct their effectiveness at every turn.
Courts will play a crucial role as well. They will need to elaborate
upon the Supreme Court’s holding in Winstar and to wrestle with the
doctrinal implications of the government’s potentially conflicting
roles as sovereign and contracting party. The Supreme Court’s feder-
alism jurisprudence could also have an indirect effect on the devel-
opment of public-private contracts. Commentators have long noted a
potential instability in the Supreme Court’s federalism jurispru-
dence: The Court’s antipathy for “coercive” federal regulation that in-
terferes with state sovereignty seems incompatible with its simulta-
neous tolerance for stringently conditioned federal grants-in-aid.
251
Conditional grants enable the federal government to regulate activi-
ties that are beyond its reach, because direct regulation would run
afoul of the Tenth Amendment.
252
Grants-in-aid have thus served as
very important mechanisms for the federal government, allowing it
to exert a powerful coercive effect on states, which in turn must su-
pervise their contracts with private providers to ensure that they
comply with federal requirements. Were the Court to curtail the fed-
eral spending power on state sovereignty grounds, it would cripple an
enormously powerful contractual accountability mechanism.
253
Thus, the courts’ role in shaping the contracting state will be con-
siderable. The judiciary will determine whether the nondelegation
doctrine forbids certain contractual delegations, delineate the extent
to which private contractors will be bound by constitutional con-
straints and statutory due process obligations, and dictate the condi-
tions under which third-party beneficiaries will have standing to
251. See Printz v. United States, 521 U.S. 898, 935 (1997) (holding that Congress can-
not circumvent New York by commanding state officials to enforce a federal regulatory
program); New York v. United States, 505 U.S. 144, 149 (1992) (finding that the federal
government cannot compel a state to take title to its radioactive waste).
252. See Printz, 521 U.S. at 898; New York, 505 U.S. at 144; South Dakota v. Dole, 483
U.S. 203 (1987).
253. See Dole, 483 U.S. at 211 (acknowledging that in cases involving conditions at-
tached to federal funding, “the financial inducement offered by Congress might be so coer-
cive as to pass the point at which ‘pressure turns into compulsion’” (quoting Charles C.
Steward Mach. Co. v. Davis, 301 U.S. 548, 590 (1937))).
214 FLORIDA STATE UNIVERSITY LAW REVIEW [Vol. 28:155
challenge the terms of public-private contracts. Taken together, the
emerging jurisprudence in all of these areas will have an enormous
impact on the future of contractual approaches to governance, even if
courts do not explicitly see themselves engaged in the project now.
The dangers of contract as an administrative and regulatory in-
strument are undeniable. Contract could be a vehicle for legislative
abdication of responsibility and fragmented accountability; it could
badly weaken the state. From an administrative law perspective,
public-private contracts may subvert important public law norms,
such as public participation in decisionmaking, rationality, fairness,
and accountability. However, in an era of inevitable public-private
interdependence, contract also presents us with a potentially effec-
tive instrument of governance and a potentially powerful account-
ability mechanism. At a minimum, the rise of public-private contract
will force legal scholars to confront the uncomfortable convergence of
public law norms and private law contract principles, a project that
holds great intellectual appeal and offers a promising agenda for fu-
ture research.